President Tiny Hands LIED about counterprotesters not having permit

Did YOU bother to read the whole link? Counter protesters didn't need a permit to be in the park.

From the link....................

Charlottesville spokeswoman Miriam I. Dickler told Moyer that only one permit was issued for Emancipation Park — the one received by white nationalists staging the “Unite the Right” rally. However, counterprotesters did not need permits to protest that rally, she said.


“Please bear in mind that people do not need a permit to enter a public park, even when another event is scheduled to take place there, nor are they required to have one to be on streets or sidewalks adjacent to or outside the park,” Dickler said in an email.


Per the spokeswoman, people don't need a permit to enter a public park, even when another event is taking place there. And, they don't need one for the streets or sidewalks adjacent either.

Yeah, the white supremacists did get their permit to hold a rally. But, the people who showed up to protest their rally didn't need a permit, because it's a public park.

A permit is required for an assembly of protesters. That's why there was a permit at all. People can come and go, but they cannot hold an event (like a protest or counterprotest) without a permit. They are first come first served. For safety reasons, protests and counterprotest are separated.

I understand that psychoboy want to the counterprotest? Can't gain a clear understanding because some sources say the WS were removed (by law enforcement) from their approved location and steered right into the CP's. The alleged murder appears to have been at the entrance/exit of one of the parks assigned to CP's.
For safety reasons, protests and counterprotest are separated.

In whose mind, do you suppose, ~400 feet one one side, and ~1000 feet on the other, "separation" in a town the size of C-ville (the vast majority of which is UVA campus and university-affiliated land), a place where one can holler that far and be heard, between groups numbering in the hundreds constitutes sufficient separation "for safety reasons" between groups like white supremacists and their opponents?

It wasn't sufficient at all! As I've said before, the police messed up! They are supposed to be separated for this very reason. If you were in charge of those permits, would you have put them that close with no barricade or wall of mounted cops? I wouldn't have. It doesn't take a psychic to know someone's going to get hurt or killed.
If you were in charge of those permits, would you have put them that close with no barricade or wall of mounted cops?

Were I in charge of issuing permits in Charlottesville, VA and aware that the permit was being requested for a white supremacist/nationalist gathering, I almost certainly wouldn't have issued white supremacists/nationalists a protesting permit -- on the grounds that hate speech isn't protected by the 1st Amendment and that it's reasonable to expect at least some of their speech would be hateful in nature -- in the town of Charlottesville. I would also have denied the counter-protesters a permit too were it apparent to me that they might attract Antifa and or white supremacist/nationalist contingents. Big cities are welcome, at their discretion, to forebear the sorts of conflagrations that result from clashes of those two groups, C-ville, and its overwhelmingly large student population, just doesn't have the resources to contain that sort of madness.

I'd have told them to submit a petition or send in written letters voicing their objections to removing the statue or reasons why it should be removed.
Did they overrule Brandenburg v. Ohio?
No; however, there's more to free speech than Brandenburg. Moreover, the scope of Brandenburg is with regard to punishment in reaction to speech made and the course of action I indicated is preemptive, thus not at all a punishment [1], and purposed upon avoiding "clear and present danger" [2] presented by the specific hate speech that would be expected to happen at white supremacist and Antifa attended public protests/events. It may be that individuals refer to the denial of a permit as a "punishment," but the law does not construe that as a punishment. It sees it as a proscription. Also, Brandenburg pertains to codes of law and regulations, not to the exercising of professional judgment, which, were I the permit issuer, is what I'd be doing in deciding to issue or withhold permits.

I believe I'd be fully justified in acting preemptively for in the wake of the Charlottesville events, we observe that Heather Heyer was killed and several others injured. As established in United States v. O'Brien, when the government promulgates a rule for reasons unrelated to the content of expression, and the governmental interests at stake are substantial, the regulation will normally be upheld even though it may have the incidental effect of interfering with speech. One may not like the "clear and present danger" test, but the fact is that it currently stands.


Let me explain the legal theory and case law that informs my arrival at the conclusion/decision above...For this post, the "main" post content provides the jurisprudential framework upon which my conclusion is based. Readers will find my application of the framework's concepts in the "Notes" section of the post. (If one doesn't read the notes in conjunction with the "main" post, one won't know and cannot understand what legal argument I've presented to justify my decision to withhold permits.)

There are two aspects of free speech (expression): affirmative and negative. The SCOTUS has recognized principles and doctrines from both aspects. The aspect that I'd used as the basis for denying a permit is, of course, the negative aspect. The two notions are well explained in Rodney Smolla's "Academic Freedom, Hate Speech, and the Idea of a University." (It's a typical length paper -- ~35 pages) Relevant excerpts are given below:

To "get it," one must understand the general framework of how freedom of speech "works" in jurisprudential consideration.

Affirmative Model of Free Speech Jurisprudence:
The "affirmative" side of first amendment jurisprudence approaches free speech issues by emphasizing a group of interrelated doctrines that have combined, in modern times, to create a constitutional jurisprudence highly protective of freedom of speech. The affirmative side begins with the mindset that speech is presumptively protected against any restraint or punishment, and regards any encroachment with intense skepticism. [3] Affirmative thinkers are unlikely to rest the justification for freedom of speech on any one theory, but instead point to a cluster of rationales for treating freedom of speech as a specially preferred social value. Most importantly, the affirmative side of first amendment jurisprudence emphasizes both the social value of free speech to the collective good and the private value of free speech to the individual. [4]

As a collective value, freedom of speech serves the general social interest in the pursuit of truth through the "marketplace of ideas. " Free speech also serves as a check on tyranny, and is the lifeblood of democratic self-governance. These collective theories justify free speech as a means to an end. But free speech is also an end in itself, an end intimately intertwined with human autonomy and dignity . Free speech is thus especially valuable for reasons that have nothing to do with the collective search for truth or the processes of self-government, or for any other conceptualization of the common good. 11 It is a right to speak one's mind defiantly, robustly, and irreverently, just because it is one's mind.'

Negative Model of Free Speech Jurisprudence:
The negative side begins with the proposition that the first amendment is not an absolute and that many recognized doctrines exist that permit speech to be regulated or punished. When presented with a problem such as hate speech, the negative first amendment thinker says: "Here are social policy values of enormous magnitude-equality, tolerance, and respect for human dignity-values that are, no less than free speech, of constitutional dimension. Let us employ every conceivable exception to protection for free expression that is currently recognized, so that hate speech can be deterred and these laudable values vindicated."

The negative first amendment thinker accepts freedom of speech as an important constitutional value, but, when matters such as hate speech are at issue, tends to look for ways to stretch the loopholes. The negative thinker will tend to punch holes in the many classic rationales that have been advanced to support expansive protection of freedom of speech. The poetic power of the marketplace image, it is pointed out, is tempered by experience. Grounding freedom of speech in individual fulfillment, it is argued, is inappropriate, for then freedom of speech becomes indistinguishable from any other human desire, losing any claim to unique shelter from interference by the state. Significantly, the negative free speech thinker is likely to single out one narrow rationale for elevating protection of free expression -- the significance of freedom of speech to the process of self-governance -- thus treating political speech as the only genre of expression meriting heightened protection.

How the SCOTUS Reconciles the two models:
The affirmative side of free speech thinking has, in recent history, more often triumphed over the negative. The SCOTUS has tended to accept the affirmative argument that freedom of speech is a preferred value supported by multiple rationales, extending generous levels of constitutional protection to a vast range of expression. Despite the marketplace metaphor's frailties, the Court has enthusiastically embraced it. The Court also has acknowledged that the first amendment "serves not only the needs of the polity but also those of the human spirit-a spirit that demands self-expression."
The predominance of the affirmative model over the negative has not, however been absolute. The area of hate speech is one dimension whereby the Court has seen fit, to grant way to some applications of the negative model. The SCOTUS evaluates matters of proscribing expression using several doctrines, some of which, drawn from the affirmative model, protect aspects and forms hate speech and others drawn from the negative model and that the Court accepts as legitimate grounds for proscribing and/or punishing hate speech. My attestation that I'd have denied the permits, obviously, derives from the Court's recognized negative principles. What are the various principles? (Read Smolla's paper for detailed discussion of what they entail and, with regard to the affirmative principles, bars one must meet overcome their forbearance of hate speech.)

Affirmative principles that protect certain hate speech:
  • Neutrality -- Mere opposition to an idea is never enough, standing alone, to justify the abridgment of speech. All ideas are created equal in the eyes of the first amendment-even those ideas that are universally condemned and run counter to constitutional principle
  • Emotion -- Speech does not forfeit the protection that it would otherwise enjoy merely because it is laced with passion or vulgarity.
  • Symbolism -- "Speech" is construed to include non-verbal expression, including demonstrations/protests and imagery.
  • Harm -- While the neutrality principle forbids penalizing speech merely because of opposition to its content, modern first amendment jurisprudence does permit speech to be penalized when it causes harm. The harm principle defines the types of injuries that will qualify as harms sufficient to justify regulation of speech. [2]
  • Causation -- The integrity of the neutrality, emotion, and harm principles is dependent upon the adoption of a rigorous causation rule that requires a close causal nexus between speech and harm before penalizing speech. [5] The modern "clear and present danger" test [established in Brandenburg] is the most famous articulation of the currently prevailing causation rule. Advocacy of force or criminal activity may not be enough unless "such advocacy is directed to inciting or producing imminent lawless action and is likely to incite or produce such action." [This is required because] Virtually any opinion might, at some indeterminate future time, "cause" physical harm. [5]
  • Precision -- A proscriptive regulation must meet two precision requirements (See also Smolla notes 34, 35, 54-58 and the corresponding text giving rise to those notes):
    • Substantive --> The regulation implicating speech be precisely designed to effectuate the governmental interest at stake. [6]
    • Definitional --> The terms used to identify proscribed speech be defined with a meticulous exactitude well beyond that of other routine legislation, so that speakers know in advance what speech is and is not permitted, thereby avoiding the self-censorship caused by uncertainty. [6]
Negative principles that allow hate speech to be restricted:
Modern first amendment jurisprudence does permit expression to be penalized in a number of circumstances applicable to hate speech. The circumstances by which hate speech can be proscribed are:
  • The Two-Class Theory -- The Court continues to treat "obscene" speech as not within the protection of the first amendment at all. Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire established that, in terms of content, only obscene speech can be proscribed under "two-class" theory.
  • The Fighting Words Doctrine -- While Chaplinksy repudiates "two-class" theory for all but obscene speech, the "fighting words" doctrine remains valid so long as the proscription meets the "clear and present danger" test. Thus a verbal attack directed at a particular individual in a face-to-face confrontation that presents a clear and present danger of a violent physical reaction may be penalized. [7] A statute aimed at hate speech that only penalizes such "fighting words" confrontations, and that is applied to require a governmental showing of imminent danger in every individual case, would be constitutional.
  • Content-Neutral Protection of Persons or Property -- The clear and present danger test permits speech to be penalized when it is on the brink of erupting into violence against persons or property. Once physical injury to persons or property has taken place, criminal and tort rules of general application may be brought to bear upon the wrongdoer, and it is no defense that the persons were injured or the property destroyed in the cause of free expression. There is no first amendment right to commit physical assault or damage another's property. Under the principles established in United States v. O'Brien, when the government promulgates a rule for reasons unrelated to the content of expression, and the governmental interests at stake are substantial, the regulation will normally be upheld even though it may have the incidental effect of interfering with speech. [8]
  • Discriminatory Conduct -- Just as the first amendment does not immunize physical attacks on persons or property, it does not immunize discriminatory conduct illegal under the equal protection clause, civil rights acts, or labor laws. As long as it is the underlying discriminatory behavior and not the speech that is being regulated, the first amendment is not offended. Under the analysis in O'Brien, the penalty exacted on speech in such cases is incidental to the governmental purpose of regulating the purely non-expressive component of the conduct. [9]
  • The Theory of Hate Speech as a Relational Harm. -- [This aspect has nothing to do with my aims, so I'm not providing a brief description for it. (See the taxonomy of harms in Note 2.)]
  • The Public Speech/Private Speech Dichotomy -- [This too doesn't apply to the situation and my proposed action.]
By this point, one should have read the framework and my notes explaining how I've applied them. If one has done so, one will observe that in choosing to deny permits to the white supremacists/nationalist and their Antifa opponents, I've applied the requisite and situationally applicable "affirmative" and "negative" free speech doctrines and tests and that I've closely adhered to SCOTUS guidance in doing so. Accordingly, I ma confident my "hypothetical" decision to withhold permits would likely stand.


Notes:
  1. See Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire. In that case, the Court explicitly recognizes discretely prevention and punishment.

    "There are certain well-defined and narrowly limited classes of speech, the prevention and punishment of which have never been thought to raise any Constitutional problem. These include the lewd and obscene, the profane, the libelous, and the insulting or 'fighting' words-those which by their very utterance inflict injury or tend to incite an immediate breach of the peace."
  2. Brandenburg essentially established the use of the "clear and present danger" test in determining whether and what speech could be interdicted or punished. The dangers themselves must fall into either or both of Category I or Category II (see below) harms from among those recognized as tortious or criminal in U.S. law (the injuries and acts that precipitate them are not, in law, construed as being mutually exclusive; for instance a Category I act/harm can often create Category II and/or III harms); harm that is solely a Category III harm is insufficient for preempting or punishing speech.

    Obviously, the category of harm I'd aim to prevent is Category I.

    (For convenience, the classes of harms recognized in U.S. law are below summarized. Some readers may care for vastly more summarized explication of the notion of "harm" than is found at the preceding links. For them, I suggest the following: Theories of Criminal Law or Freedom of Speech)
    • Taxonomy of Harms (Examples provided for harm classes relevant to the types of harm I, in opting to deny a permit, foresee as "clear and present" harms I reasonably expect to result were I instead to issue the permit and the applicants to assemble and express themselves. From a reactive standpoint, punishment, the ones I anticipate need not be the ones that indeed resulted.)
      • Category I -- Physical Harms.
        • Injuries to persons -- Examples:
          • Solicitation of murder
          • Incitement to riot on behalf of the speaker's cause
          • Reactive violence against a speaker in response to their message
        • Injuries to property -- Examples:
          • Solicitation of arson
          • Incitement to destroy property
          • Reactive violence against the property of the speaker in response to the message
      • Category II -- Relational Harms -- Some of these may occur, but I don't think one, I, can reasonably anticipate that they would merely as a result of a public protest or other socio-political gathering of the sort here under discussion and the accompanying expressions made there.
        • Injuries to social relationahips
        • Injuries to transactions or business relationships
        • Injuries to information ownership interests
        • Injuries to interests in confidentiality
      • Category III -- Reactive Harms
        • Injuries to individual emotional tranquility -- Roughly speaking, this amounts to one's getting their feelings hurt or suffering embarrassment
        • Injuries to communal sensibilities -- Roughly speaking, this amounts to one's being aghast at something expressed as some people claimed to be when Janet Jackson had a "wardrobe malfunction."
  3. Once again, positive and negative liberty rear their heads.
  4. One can get a sense of what Emerson covers in his book (I linked it, but I can't find a free version of it) in his paper "Toward a General Theory of the First Amendment."
  5. "Penalise" and "indeterminate" -- Observe that:
    1. The temporal context and focus is penalizing not proscribing/preempting hate speech. Penalizing anything is necessarily reactive, not proactive. Penalty requires an operative and extant actus rea wherefore courts can penalize its actor.
    2. The temporal context for determining whether the harm be "present" cannot be indeterminate. It need not be a precise hour and minute. In the matters of protests, having a timeframe reasonably proximate to the event itself -- in the setup of the event, during the event, in the dismantling of the event -- is sufficiently specific for this test.

      That harm may occur days or weeks prior to or following the noted periods is not sufficient. I would not be justified in denying a permit because I think some "nut job" may, the day before the event, say, riot in the streets or "raid" the hotel where many (counter-) protesters are bivouacked.
  6. SCOTUS asserted in Sable Communications of California, Inc. v FCC that government may only "regulate the content of constitutionally protected speech in order to promote a compelling interest if it chooses the least restrictive means to further the articulated interest." Also, U.S. v O'Brien established that "when government regulation is 'unrelated to the suppression of free expression,' the "incidental restriction on alleged First Amendment freedoms" must be "no greater than is essential to the furtherance of that interest."

    In denying the permit, I have no aim to regulate the content of the speech (definitional aspect) that might be presented. My reason for denying the permit is "unrelated to the suppression of free expression" in that I find that the town of C-ville hasn't the resources to manage the event and ensure the safety of the attendees. My reason for denying the permit is to prevent the "clear and present" risk of physical harm from materializing into reality (substantive aspect). Given my motives, the precision principle's substance provision applies and the definitional one does not. Anticipating and preventing harm such as that which happened to Heather Heyer is valid, given the C-ville resource paucity, as a basis for denying the permit.

    It's probably worth noting that whereas I'd not have issued the permit, C-ville opted to issue a permit and then revoke it. Ms. Heyer would be alive were they to have anticipated the violence and denied the permit, but it's too late for that now. As for on what basis one might foresee the violence, well, I'll leave it to you and other readers to search the Internet for examples of the violence that results when white supremacists march and/or host public demonstrations, rallies and protests. For my part, I'll note that just as C. Cantwell was able to anticipate the harm, so can I, the difference being that as the issuer of the permit, I'd have been in a position to avert it rather than inspire or commit it.
  7. Notice that again that the scope is with regard to a regulation or statue, something that applies "universally" within a jurisdiction, not the discrete and expedient exercise of professional judgment.
  8. This provision must be applied evenly. It is in recognition of that requirement that I wrote what I did about also denying permits to the Antifa.
  9. Here again I repeat, I would deny the permit due to the risk of violence erupting as a result of the speech, not to proscribe the speech itself.


Aside:
I guess people, you, WillHaftawaite, think I just post "sh*t" becuase it happens across my mind. Trust me. On the occasions that I do that, I'll, along with whatever idea I share, volunteer that I have remarked off the top of my head and without confirmation of the idea(s) I share.

I absolutely thought about and confirmed the plausible and probable legal validity my remarks on "permit denial" before I posted them. I might have missed something, but this isn't it. It arrive at my conclusion merely because I don't like white supremacists. As much as I "bitch and moan" about others not researching/confirming what they believe be so prior to posting their beliefs, you had to know that I did do so. FWIW, on the free speech topic, the research was done ages and ages ago; all I really had to do was "dig it up" and quickly review it.

Lastly, several folks have griped about the length of my posts. The ones that are long when I conceive them are the ones that I have a sense that a notable share of readers here may not be deeply familiar with the topic or aspect of it I've chosen to discuss. Others, like this one, are long because I initially posted something short and someone responded to it with remarks that bid to explain/justify the rational basis giving rise to the initial brief post. As goes the current topic, I thought, given how often the free speech topic appears on USMB and in "real life," "everyone" here is very well/deeply versed on the legal theory, case law, and applications of free speech principles and so on. Clearly, I was mistaken.

By the same token, I don't think the other member's tacit request that I explain myself was out of line or rudely made, so I don't mind, in such instances, doing so. I'd thought about it before I posted the "short comments," so it's not bother to share those thoughts.
 
A permit is required for an assembly of protesters. That's why there was a permit at all. People can come and go, but they cannot hold an event (like a protest or counterprotest) without a permit. They are first come first served. For safety reasons, protests and counterprotest are separated.

I understand that psychoboy want to the counterprotest? Can't gain a clear understanding because some sources say the WS were removed (by law enforcement) from their approved location and steered right into the CP's. The alleged murder appears to have been at the entrance/exit of one of the parks assigned to CP's.
For safety reasons, protests and counterprotest are separated.

In whose mind, do you suppose, ~400 feet one one side, and ~1000 feet on the other, "separation" in a town the size of C-ville (the vast majority of which is UVA campus and university-affiliated land), a place where one can holler that far and be heard, between groups numbering in the hundreds constitutes sufficient separation "for safety reasons" between groups like white supremacists and their opponents?

It wasn't sufficient at all! As I've said before, the police messed up! They are supposed to be separated for this very reason. If you were in charge of those permits, would you have put them that close with no barricade or wall of mounted cops? I wouldn't have. It doesn't take a psychic to know someone's going to get hurt or killed.
If you were in charge of those permits, would you have put them that close with no barricade or wall of mounted cops?

Were I in charge of issuing permits in Charlottesville, VA and aware that the permit was being requested for a white supremacist/nationalist gathering, I almost certainly wouldn't have issued white supremacists/nationalists a protesting permit -- on the grounds that hate speech isn't protected by the 1st Amendment and that it's reasonable to expect at least some of their speech would be hateful in nature -- in the town of Charlottesville. I would also have denied the counter-protesters a permit too were it apparent to me that they might attract Antifa and or white supremacist/nationalist contingents. Big cities are welcome, at their discretion, to forebear the sorts of conflagrations that result from clashes of those two groups, C-ville, and its overwhelmingly large student population, just doesn't have the resources to contain that sort of madness.

I'd have told them to submit a petition or send in written letters voicing their objections to removing the statue or reasons why it should be removed.
Did they overrule Brandenburg v. Ohio?
No; however, there's more to free speech than Brandenburg. Moreover, the scope of Brandenburg is with regard to punishment in reaction to speech made and the course of action I indicated is preemptive, thus not at all a punishment [1], and purposed upon avoiding "clear and present danger" [2] presented by the specific hate speech that would be expected to happen at white supremacist and Antifa attended public protests/events. It may be that individuals refer to the denial of a permit as a "punishment," but the law does not construe that as a punishment. It sees it as a proscription. Also, Brandenburg pertains to codes of law and regulations, not to the exercising of professional judgment, which, were I the permit issuer, is what I'd be doing in deciding to issue or withhold permits.

I believe I'd be fully justified in acting preemptively for in the wake of the Charlottesville events, we observe that Heather Heyer was killed and several others injured. As established in United States v. O'Brien, when the government promulgates a rule for reasons unrelated to the content of expression, and the governmental interests at stake are substantial, the regulation will normally be upheld even though it may have the incidental effect of interfering with speech. One may not like the "clear and present danger" test, but the fact is that it currently stands.


Let me explain the legal theory and case law that informs my arrival at the conclusion/decision above...For this post, the "main" post content provides the jurisprudential framework upon which my conclusion is based. Readers will find my application of the framework's concepts in the "Notes" section of the post. (If one doesn't read the notes in conjunction with the "main" post, one won't know and cannot understand what legal argument I've presented to justify my decision to withhold permits.)

There are two aspects of free speech (expression): affirmative and negative. The SCOTUS has recognized principles and doctrines from both aspects. The aspect that I'd used as the basis for denying a permit is, of course, the negative aspect. The two notions are well explained in Rodney Smolla's "Academic Freedom, Hate Speech, and the Idea of a University." (It's a typical length paper -- ~35 pages) Relevant excerpts are given below:

To "get it," one must understand the general framework of how freedom of speech "works" in jurisprudential consideration.

Affirmative Model of Free Speech Jurisprudence:
The "affirmative" side of first amendment jurisprudence approaches free speech issues by emphasizing a group of interrelated doctrines that have combined, in modern times, to create a constitutional jurisprudence highly protective of freedom of speech. The affirmative side begins with the mindset that speech is presumptively protected against any restraint or punishment, and regards any encroachment with intense skepticism. [3] Affirmative thinkers are unlikely to rest the justification for freedom of speech on any one theory, but instead point to a cluster of rationales for treating freedom of speech as a specially preferred social value. Most importantly, the affirmative side of first amendment jurisprudence emphasizes both the social value of free speech to the collective good and the private value of free speech to the individual. [4]

As a collective value, freedom of speech serves the general social interest in the pursuit of truth through the "marketplace of ideas. " Free speech also serves as a check on tyranny, and is the lifeblood of democratic self-governance. These collective theories justify free speech as a means to an end. But free speech is also an end in itself, an end intimately intertwined with human autonomy and dignity . Free speech is thus especially valuable for reasons that have nothing to do with the collective search for truth or the processes of self-government, or for any other conceptualization of the common good. 11 It is a right to speak one's mind defiantly, robustly, and irreverently, just because it is one's mind.'

Negative Model of Free Speech Jurisprudence:
The negative side begins with the proposition that the first amendment is not an absolute and that many recognized doctrines exist that permit speech to be regulated or punished. When presented with a problem such as hate speech, the negative first amendment thinker says: "Here are social policy values of enormous magnitude-equality, tolerance, and respect for human dignity-values that are, no less than free speech, of constitutional dimension. Let us employ every conceivable exception to protection for free expression that is currently recognized, so that hate speech can be deterred and these laudable values vindicated."

The negative first amendment thinker accepts freedom of speech as an important constitutional value, but, when matters such as hate speech are at issue, tends to look for ways to stretch the loopholes. The negative thinker will tend to punch holes in the many classic rationales that have been advanced to support expansive protection of freedom of speech. The poetic power of the marketplace image, it is pointed out, is tempered by experience. Grounding freedom of speech in individual fulfillment, it is argued, is inappropriate, for then freedom of speech becomes indistinguishable from any other human desire, losing any claim to unique shelter from interference by the state. Significantly, the negative free speech thinker is likely to single out one narrow rationale for elevating protection of free expression -- the significance of freedom of speech to the process of self-governance -- thus treating political speech as the only genre of expression meriting heightened protection.

How the SCOTUS Reconciles the two models:
The affirmative side of free speech thinking has, in recent history, more often triumphed over the negative. The SCOTUS has tended to accept the affirmative argument that freedom of speech is a preferred value supported by multiple rationales, extending generous levels of constitutional protection to a vast range of expression. Despite the marketplace metaphor's frailties, the Court has enthusiastically embraced it. The Court also has acknowledged that the first amendment "serves not only the needs of the polity but also those of the human spirit-a spirit that demands self-expression."
The predominance of the affirmative model over the negative has not, however been absolute. The area of hate speech is one dimension whereby the Court has seen fit, to grant way to some applications of the negative model. The SCOTUS evaluates matters of proscribing expression using several doctrines, some of which, drawn from the affirmative model, protect aspects and forms hate speech and others drawn from the negative model and that the Court accepts as legitimate grounds for proscribing and/or punishing hate speech. My attestation that I'd have denied the permits, obviously, derives from the Court's recognized negative principles. What are the various principles? (Read Smolla's paper for detailed discussion of what they entail and, with regard to the affirmative principles, bars one must meet overcome their forbearance of hate speech.)

Affirmative principles that protect certain hate speech:
  • Neutrality -- Mere opposition to an idea is never enough, standing alone, to justify the abridgment of speech. All ideas are created equal in the eyes of the first amendment-even those ideas that are universally condemned and run counter to constitutional principle
  • Emotion -- Speech does not forfeit the protection that it would otherwise enjoy merely because it is laced with passion or vulgarity.
  • Symbolism -- "Speech" is construed to include non-verbal expression, including demonstrations/protests and imagery.
  • Harm -- While the neutrality principle forbids penalizing speech merely because of opposition to its content, modern first amendment jurisprudence does permit speech to be penalized when it causes harm. The harm principle defines the types of injuries that will qualify as harms sufficient to justify regulation of speech. [2]
  • Causation -- The integrity of the neutrality, emotion, and harm principles is dependent upon the adoption of a rigorous causation rule that requires a close causal nexus between speech and harm before penalizing speech. [5] The modern "clear and present danger" test [established in Brandenburg] is the most famous articulation of the currently prevailing causation rule. Advocacy of force or criminal activity may not be enough unless "such advocacy is directed to inciting or producing imminent lawless action and is likely to incite or produce such action." [This is required because] Virtually any opinion might, at some indeterminate future time, "cause" physical harm. [5]
  • Precision -- A proscriptive regulation must meet two precision requirements (See also Smolla notes 34, 35, 54-58 and the corresponding text giving rise to those notes):
    • Substantive --> The regulation implicating speech be precisely designed to effectuate the governmental interest at stake. [6]
    • Definitional --> The terms used to identify proscribed speech be defined with a meticulous exactitude well beyond that of other routine legislation, so that speakers know in advance what speech is and is not permitted, thereby avoiding the self-censorship caused by uncertainty. [6]
Negative principles that allow hate speech to be restricted:
Modern first amendment jurisprudence does permit expression to be penalized in a number of circumstances applicable to hate speech. The circumstances by which hate speech can be proscribed are:
  • The Two-Class Theory -- The Court continues to treat "obscene" speech as not within the protection of the first amendment at all. Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire established that, in terms of content, only obscene speech can be proscribed under "two-class" theory.
  • The Fighting Words Doctrine -- While Chaplinksy repudiates "two-class" theory for all but obscene speech, the "fighting words" doctrine remains valid so long as the proscription meets the "clear and present danger" test. Thus a verbal attack directed at a particular individual in a face-to-face confrontation that presents a clear and present danger of a violent physical reaction may be penalized. [7] A statute aimed at hate speech that only penalizes such "fighting words" confrontations, and that is applied to require a governmental showing of imminent danger in every individual case, would be constitutional.
  • Content-Neutral Protection of Persons or Property -- The clear and present danger test permits speech to be penalized when it is on the brink of erupting into violence against persons or property. Once physical injury to persons or property has taken place, criminal and tort rules of general application may be brought to bear upon the wrongdoer, and it is no defense that the persons were injured or the property destroyed in the cause of free expression. There is no first amendment right to commit physical assault or damage another's property. Under the principles established in United States v. O'Brien, when the government promulgates a rule for reasons unrelated to the content of expression, and the governmental interests at stake are substantial, the regulation will normally be upheld even though it may have the incidental effect of interfering with speech. [8]
  • Discriminatory Conduct -- Just as the first amendment does not immunize physical attacks on persons or property, it does not immunize discriminatory conduct illegal under the equal protection clause, civil rights acts, or labor laws. As long as it is the underlying discriminatory behavior and not the speech that is being regulated, the first amendment is not offended. Under the analysis in O'Brien, the penalty exacted on speech in such cases is incidental to the governmental purpose of regulating the purely non-expressive component of the conduct. [9]
  • The Theory of Hate Speech as a Relational Harm. -- [This aspect has nothing to do with my aims, so I'm not providing a brief description for it. (See the taxonomy of harms in Note 2.)]
  • The Public Speech/Private Speech Dichotomy -- [This too doesn't apply to the situation and my proposed action.]
By this point, one should have read the framework and my notes explaining how I've applied them. If one has done so, one will observe that in choosing to deny permits to the white supremacists/nationalist and their Antifa opponents, I've applied the requisite and situationally applicable "affirmative" and "negative" free speech doctrines and tests and that I've closely adhered to SCOTUS guidance in doing so. Accordingly, I ma confident my "hypothetical" decision to withhold permits would likely stand.


Notes:
  1. See Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire. In that case, the Court explicitly recognizes discretely prevention and punishment.

    "There are certain well-defined and narrowly limited classes of speech, the prevention and punishment of which have never been thought to raise any Constitutional problem. These include the lewd and obscene, the profane, the libelous, and the insulting or 'fighting' words-those which by their very utterance inflict injury or tend to incite an immediate breach of the peace."
  2. Brandenburg essentially established the use of the "clear and present danger" test in determining whether and what speech could be interdicted or punished. The dangers themselves must fall into either or both of Category I or Category II (see below) harms from among those recognized as tortious or criminal in U.S. law (the injuries and acts that precipitate them are not, in law, construed as being mutually exclusive; for instance a Category I act/harm can often create Category II and/or III harms); harm that is solely a Category III harm is insufficient for preempting or punishing speech.

    Obviously, the category of harm I'd aim to prevent is Category I.

    (For convenience, the classes of harms recognized in U.S. law are below summarized. Some readers may care for vastly more summarized explication of the notion of "harm" than is found at the preceding links. For them, I suggest the following: Theories of Criminal Law or Freedom of Speech)
    • Taxonomy of Harms (Examples provided for harm classes relevant to the types of harm I, in opting to deny a permit, foresee as "clear and present" harms I reasonably expect to result were I instead to issue the permit and the applicants to assemble and express themselves. From a reactive standpoint, punishment, the ones I anticipate need not be the ones that indeed resulted.)
      • Category I -- Physical Harms.
        • Injuries to persons -- Examples:
          • Solicitation of murder
          • Incitement to riot on behalf of the speaker's cause
          • Reactive violence against a speaker in response to their message
        • Injuries to property -- Examples:
          • Solicitation of arson
          • Incitement to destroy property
          • Reactive violence against the property of the speaker in response to the message
      • Category II -- Relational Harms -- Some of these may occur, but I don't think one, I, can reasonably anticipate that they would merely as a result of a public protest or other socio-political gathering of the sort here under discussion and the accompanying expressions made there.
        • Injuries to social relationahips
        • Injuries to transactions or business relationships
        • Injuries to information ownership interests
        • Injuries to interests in confidentiality
      • Category III -- Reactive Harms
        • Injuries to individual emotional tranquility -- Roughly speaking, this amounts to one's getting their feelings hurt or suffering embarrassment
        • Injuries to communal sensibilities -- Roughly speaking, this amounts to one's being aghast at something expressed as some people claimed to be when Janet Jackson had a "wardrobe malfunction."
  3. Once again, positive and negative liberty rear their heads.
  4. One can get a sense of what Emerson covers in his book (I linked it, but I can't find a free version of it) in his paper "Toward a General Theory of the First Amendment."
  5. "Penalise" and "indeterminate" -- Observe that:
    1. The temporal context and focus is penalizing not proscribing/preempting hate speech. Penalizing anything is necessarily reactive, not proactive. Penalty requires an operative and extant actus rea wherefore courts can penalize its actor.
    2. The temporal context for determining whether the harm be "present" cannot be indeterminate. It need not be a precise hour and minute. In the matters of protests, having a timeframe reasonably proximate to the event itself -- in the setup of the event, during the event, in the dismantling of the event -- is sufficiently specific for this test.

      That harm may occur days or weeks prior to or following the noted periods is not sufficient. I would not be justified in denying a permit because I think some "nut job" may, the day before the event, say, riot in the streets or "raid" the hotel where many (counter-) protesters are bivouacked.
  6. SCOTUS asserted in Sable Communications of California, Inc. v FCC that government may only "regulate the content of constitutionally protected speech in order to promote a compelling interest if it chooses the least restrictive means to further the articulated interest." Also, U.S. v O'Brien established that "when government regulation is 'unrelated to the suppression of free expression,' the "incidental restriction on alleged First Amendment freedoms" must be "no greater than is essential to the furtherance of that interest."

    In denying the permit, I have no aim to regulate the content of the speech (definitional aspect) that might be presented. My reason for denying the permit is "unrelated to the suppression of free expression" in that I find that the town of C-ville hasn't the resources to manage the event and ensure the safety of the attendees. My reason for denying the permit is to prevent the "clear and present" risk of physical harm from materializing into reality (substantive aspect). Given my motives, the precision principle's substance provision applies and the definitional one does not. Anticipating and preventing harm such as that which happened to Heather Heyer is valid, given the C-ville resource paucity, as a basis for denying the permit.

    It's probably worth noting that whereas I'd not have issued the permit, C-ville opted to issue a permit and then revoke it. Ms. Heyer would be alive were they to have anticipated the violence and denied the permit, but it's too late for that now. As for on what basis one might foresee the violence, well, I'll leave it to you and other readers to search the Internet for examples of the violence that results when white supremacists march and/or host public demonstrations, rallies and protests. For my part, I'll note that just as C. Cantwell was able to anticipate the harm, so can I, the difference being that as the issuer of the permit, I'd have been in a position to avert it rather than inspire or commit it.
  7. Notice that again that the scope is with regard to a regulation or statue, something that applies "universally" within a jurisdiction, not the discrete and expedient exercise of professional judgment.
  8. This provision must be applied evenly. It is in recognition of that requirement that I wrote what I did about also denying permits to the Antifa.
  9. Here again I repeat, I would deny the permit due to the risk of violence erupting as a result of the speech, not to proscribe the speech itself.


Aside:
I guess people, you, WillHaftawaite, think I just post "sh*t" becuase it happens across my mind. Trust me. On the occasions that I do that, I'll, along with whatever idea I share, volunteer that I have remarked off the top of my head and without confirmation of the idea(s) I share.

I absolutely thought about and confirmed the plausible and probable legal validity my remarks on "permit denial" before I posted them. I might have missed something, but this isn't it. It arrive at my conclusion merely because I don't like white supremacists. As much as I "bitch and moan" about others not researching/confirming what they believe be so prior to posting their beliefs, you had to know that I did do so. FWIW, on the free speech topic, the research was done ages and ages ago; all I really had to do was "dig it up" and quickly review it.

Lastly, several folks have griped about the length of my posts. The ones that are long when I conceive them are the ones that I have a sense that a notable share of readers here may not be deeply familiar with the topic or aspect of it I've chosen to discuss. Others, like this one, are long because I initially posted something short and someone responded to it with remarks that bid to explain/justify the rational basis giving rise to the initial brief post. As goes the current topic, I thought, given how often the free speech topic appears on USMB and in "real life," "everyone" here is very well/deeply versed on the legal theory, case law, and applications of free speech principles and so on. Clearly, I was mistaken.

By the same token, I don't think the other member's tacit request that I explain myself was out of line or rudely made, so I don't mind, in such instances, doing so. I'd thought about it before I posted the "short comments," so it's not bother to share those thoughts.
giphy.gif


Sorry...

fell asleep somewhere around paragraph 10
 
Did YOU bother to read the whole link? Counter protesters didn't need a permit to be in the park.

From the link....................

Charlottesville spokeswoman Miriam I. Dickler told Moyer that only one permit was issued for Emancipation Park — the one received by white nationalists staging the “Unite the Right” rally. However, counterprotesters did not need permits to protest that rally, she said.


“Please bear in mind that people do not need a permit to enter a public park, even when another event is scheduled to take place there, nor are they required to have one to be on streets or sidewalks adjacent to or outside the park,” Dickler said in an email.


Per the spokeswoman, people don't need a permit to enter a public park, even when another event is taking place there. And, they don't need one for the streets or sidewalks adjacent either.

Yeah, the white supremacists did get their permit to hold a rally. But, the people who showed up to protest their rally didn't need a permit, because it's a public park.

A permit is required for an assembly of protesters. That's why there was a permit at all. People can come and go, but they cannot hold an event (like a protest or counterprotest) without a permit. They are first come first served. For safety reasons, protests and counterprotest are separated.

I understand that psychoboy want to the counterprotest? Can't gain a clear understanding because some sources say the WS were removed (by law enforcement) from their approved location and steered right into the CP's. The alleged murder appears to have been at the entrance/exit of one of the parks assigned to CP's.
For safety reasons, protests and counterprotest are separated.

In whose mind, do you suppose, ~400 feet one one side, and ~1000 feet on the other, "separation" in a town the size of C-ville (the vast majority of which is UVA campus and university-affiliated land), a place where one can holler that far and be heard, between groups numbering in the hundreds constitutes sufficient separation "for safety reasons" between groups like white supremacists and their opponents?

It wasn't sufficient at all! As I've said before, the police messed up! They are supposed to be separated for this very reason. If you were in charge of those permits, would you have put them that close with no barricade or wall of mounted cops? I wouldn't have. It doesn't take a psychic to know someone's going to get hurt or killed.
If you were in charge of those permits, would you have put them that close with no barricade or wall of mounted cops?

Were I in charge of issuing permits in Charlottesville, VA and aware that the permit was being requested for a white supremacist/nationalist gathering, I almost certainly wouldn't have issued white supremacists/nationalists a protesting permit -- on the grounds that hate speech isn't protected by the 1st Amendment and that it's reasonable to expect at least some of their speech would be hateful in nature -- in the town of Charlottesville. I would also have denied the counter-protesters a permit too were it apparent to me that they might attract Antifa and or white supremacist/nationalist contingents. Big cities are welcome, at their discretion, to forebear the sorts of conflagrations that result from clashes of those two groups, C-ville, and its overwhelmingly large student population, just doesn't have the resources to contain that sort of madness.

I'd have told them to submit a petition or send in written letters voicing their objections to removing the statue or reasons why it should be removed.
Question: Fox pundits declare at least once per hour that hate speech is protected. I've heard it other places than Fox, as well. Are you sure hate speech isn't protected? Speech inciting violence isn't, but how often has that shut down these people?

It is and, in certain instances, it isn't. See post 81 (when you have time; it's a long read) for why I think denying the permits would be upheld. The Smolla document I referenced/cited in it is one that's well worth keeping handy. It's first section provides an excellent and brief overview of under what circumstances the SCOTUS allows expressions of hate to be penalized and/or proscribed, both in codified law/regulations and in the exercise of discrete and expeditious judgment.

It's worth noting that although I made my "permit" decision/statements with observance of the "discriminatory conduct" principle, insofar as the hypothetical scenario I posed may indeed be "a first" were it adhered to in C-ville, that principle may not even have applied were the actual C-ville permit issuer(s) to have refused to grant permits to the parties involved. If it were "a first," whatever they do would set a precedent for future action.

Precedents aren't monolithic, but neither can one arbitrarily and capriciously set them "today," reject them "tomorrow" and on the next day revert back to the original. Doing so contravenes the notion of there being a principle, a precedent or set thereof by which one is guided.
 
In whose mind, do you suppose, ~400 feet one one side, and ~1000 feet on the other, "separation" in a town the size of C-ville (the vast majority of which is UVA campus and university-affiliated land), a place where one can holler that far and be heard, between groups numbering in the hundreds constitutes sufficient separation "for safety reasons" between groups like white supremacists and their opponents?

It wasn't sufficient at all! As I've said before, the police messed up! They are supposed to be separated for this very reason. If you were in charge of those permits, would you have put them that close with no barricade or wall of mounted cops? I wouldn't have. It doesn't take a psychic to know someone's going to get hurt or killed.
If you were in charge of those permits, would you have put them that close with no barricade or wall of mounted cops?

Were I in charge of issuing permits in Charlottesville, VA and aware that the permit was being requested for a white supremacist/nationalist gathering, I almost certainly wouldn't have issued white supremacists/nationalists a protesting permit -- on the grounds that hate speech isn't protected by the 1st Amendment and that it's reasonable to expect at least some of their speech would be hateful in nature -- in the town of Charlottesville. I would also have denied the counter-protesters a permit too were it apparent to me that they might attract Antifa and or white supremacist/nationalist contingents. Big cities are welcome, at their discretion, to forebear the sorts of conflagrations that result from clashes of those two groups, C-ville, and its overwhelmingly large student population, just doesn't have the resources to contain that sort of madness.

I'd have told them to submit a petition or send in written letters voicing their objections to removing the statue or reasons why it should be removed.
Did they overrule Brandenburg v. Ohio?
No; however, there's more to free speech than Brandenburg. Moreover, the scope of Brandenburg is with regard to punishment in reaction to speech made and the course of action I indicated is preemptive, thus not at all a punishment [1], and purposed upon avoiding "clear and present danger" [2] presented by the specific hate speech that would be expected to happen at white supremacist and Antifa attended public protests/events. It may be that individuals refer to the denial of a permit as a "punishment," but the law does not construe that as a punishment. It sees it as a proscription. Also, Brandenburg pertains to codes of law and regulations, not to the exercising of professional judgment, which, were I the permit issuer, is what I'd be doing in deciding to issue or withhold permits.

I believe I'd be fully justified in acting preemptively for in the wake of the Charlottesville events, we observe that Heather Heyer was killed and several others injured. As established in United States v. O'Brien, when the government promulgates a rule for reasons unrelated to the content of expression, and the governmental interests at stake are substantial, the regulation will normally be upheld even though it may have the incidental effect of interfering with speech. One may not like the "clear and present danger" test, but the fact is that it currently stands.


Let me explain the legal theory and case law that informs my arrival at the conclusion/decision above...For this post, the "main" post content provides the jurisprudential framework upon which my conclusion is based. Readers will find my application of the framework's concepts in the "Notes" section of the post. (If one doesn't read the notes in conjunction with the "main" post, one won't know and cannot understand what legal argument I've presented to justify my decision to withhold permits.)

There are two aspects of free speech (expression): affirmative and negative. The SCOTUS has recognized principles and doctrines from both aspects. The aspect that I'd used as the basis for denying a permit is, of course, the negative aspect. The two notions are well explained in Rodney Smolla's "Academic Freedom, Hate Speech, and the Idea of a University." (It's a typical length paper -- ~35 pages) Relevant excerpts are given below:

To "get it," one must understand the general framework of how freedom of speech "works" in jurisprudential consideration.

Affirmative Model of Free Speech Jurisprudence:
The "affirmative" side of first amendment jurisprudence approaches free speech issues by emphasizing a group of interrelated doctrines that have combined, in modern times, to create a constitutional jurisprudence highly protective of freedom of speech. The affirmative side begins with the mindset that speech is presumptively protected against any restraint or punishment, and regards any encroachment with intense skepticism. [3] Affirmative thinkers are unlikely to rest the justification for freedom of speech on any one theory, but instead point to a cluster of rationales for treating freedom of speech as a specially preferred social value. Most importantly, the affirmative side of first amendment jurisprudence emphasizes both the social value of free speech to the collective good and the private value of free speech to the individual. [4]

As a collective value, freedom of speech serves the general social interest in the pursuit of truth through the "marketplace of ideas. " Free speech also serves as a check on tyranny, and is the lifeblood of democratic self-governance. These collective theories justify free speech as a means to an end. But free speech is also an end in itself, an end intimately intertwined with human autonomy and dignity . Free speech is thus especially valuable for reasons that have nothing to do with the collective search for truth or the processes of self-government, or for any other conceptualization of the common good. 11 It is a right to speak one's mind defiantly, robustly, and irreverently, just because it is one's mind.'

Negative Model of Free Speech Jurisprudence:
The negative side begins with the proposition that the first amendment is not an absolute and that many recognized doctrines exist that permit speech to be regulated or punished. When presented with a problem such as hate speech, the negative first amendment thinker says: "Here are social policy values of enormous magnitude-equality, tolerance, and respect for human dignity-values that are, no less than free speech, of constitutional dimension. Let us employ every conceivable exception to protection for free expression that is currently recognized, so that hate speech can be deterred and these laudable values vindicated."

The negative first amendment thinker accepts freedom of speech as an important constitutional value, but, when matters such as hate speech are at issue, tends to look for ways to stretch the loopholes. The negative thinker will tend to punch holes in the many classic rationales that have been advanced to support expansive protection of freedom of speech. The poetic power of the marketplace image, it is pointed out, is tempered by experience. Grounding freedom of speech in individual fulfillment, it is argued, is inappropriate, for then freedom of speech becomes indistinguishable from any other human desire, losing any claim to unique shelter from interference by the state. Significantly, the negative free speech thinker is likely to single out one narrow rationale for elevating protection of free expression -- the significance of freedom of speech to the process of self-governance -- thus treating political speech as the only genre of expression meriting heightened protection.

How the SCOTUS Reconciles the two models:
The affirmative side of free speech thinking has, in recent history, more often triumphed over the negative. The SCOTUS has tended to accept the affirmative argument that freedom of speech is a preferred value supported by multiple rationales, extending generous levels of constitutional protection to a vast range of expression. Despite the marketplace metaphor's frailties, the Court has enthusiastically embraced it. The Court also has acknowledged that the first amendment "serves not only the needs of the polity but also those of the human spirit-a spirit that demands self-expression."
The predominance of the affirmative model over the negative has not, however been absolute. The area of hate speech is one dimension whereby the Court has seen fit, to grant way to some applications of the negative model. The SCOTUS evaluates matters of proscribing expression using several doctrines, some of which, drawn from the affirmative model, protect aspects and forms hate speech and others drawn from the negative model and that the Court accepts as legitimate grounds for proscribing and/or punishing hate speech. My attestation that I'd have denied the permits, obviously, derives from the Court's recognized negative principles. What are the various principles? (Read Smolla's paper for detailed discussion of what they entail and, with regard to the affirmative principles, bars one must meet overcome their forbearance of hate speech.)

Affirmative principles that protect certain hate speech:
  • Neutrality -- Mere opposition to an idea is never enough, standing alone, to justify the abridgment of speech. All ideas are created equal in the eyes of the first amendment-even those ideas that are universally condemned and run counter to constitutional principle
  • Emotion -- Speech does not forfeit the protection that it would otherwise enjoy merely because it is laced with passion or vulgarity.
  • Symbolism -- "Speech" is construed to include non-verbal expression, including demonstrations/protests and imagery.
  • Harm -- While the neutrality principle forbids penalizing speech merely because of opposition to its content, modern first amendment jurisprudence does permit speech to be penalized when it causes harm. The harm principle defines the types of injuries that will qualify as harms sufficient to justify regulation of speech. [2]
  • Causation -- The integrity of the neutrality, emotion, and harm principles is dependent upon the adoption of a rigorous causation rule that requires a close causal nexus between speech and harm before penalizing speech. [5] The modern "clear and present danger" test [established in Brandenburg] is the most famous articulation of the currently prevailing causation rule. Advocacy of force or criminal activity may not be enough unless "such advocacy is directed to inciting or producing imminent lawless action and is likely to incite or produce such action." [This is required because] Virtually any opinion might, at some indeterminate future time, "cause" physical harm. [5]
  • Precision -- A proscriptive regulation must meet two precision requirements (See also Smolla notes 34, 35, 54-58 and the corresponding text giving rise to those notes):
    • Substantive --> The regulation implicating speech be precisely designed to effectuate the governmental interest at stake. [6]
    • Definitional --> The terms used to identify proscribed speech be defined with a meticulous exactitude well beyond that of other routine legislation, so that speakers know in advance what speech is and is not permitted, thereby avoiding the self-censorship caused by uncertainty. [6]
Negative principles that allow hate speech to be restricted:
Modern first amendment jurisprudence does permit expression to be penalized in a number of circumstances applicable to hate speech. The circumstances by which hate speech can be proscribed are:
  • The Two-Class Theory -- The Court continues to treat "obscene" speech as not within the protection of the first amendment at all. Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire established that, in terms of content, only obscene speech can be proscribed under "two-class" theory.
  • The Fighting Words Doctrine -- While Chaplinksy repudiates "two-class" theory for all but obscene speech, the "fighting words" doctrine remains valid so long as the proscription meets the "clear and present danger" test. Thus a verbal attack directed at a particular individual in a face-to-face confrontation that presents a clear and present danger of a violent physical reaction may be penalized. [7] A statute aimed at hate speech that only penalizes such "fighting words" confrontations, and that is applied to require a governmental showing of imminent danger in every individual case, would be constitutional.
  • Content-Neutral Protection of Persons or Property -- The clear and present danger test permits speech to be penalized when it is on the brink of erupting into violence against persons or property. Once physical injury to persons or property has taken place, criminal and tort rules of general application may be brought to bear upon the wrongdoer, and it is no defense that the persons were injured or the property destroyed in the cause of free expression. There is no first amendment right to commit physical assault or damage another's property. Under the principles established in United States v. O'Brien, when the government promulgates a rule for reasons unrelated to the content of expression, and the governmental interests at stake are substantial, the regulation will normally be upheld even though it may have the incidental effect of interfering with speech. [8]
  • Discriminatory Conduct -- Just as the first amendment does not immunize physical attacks on persons or property, it does not immunize discriminatory conduct illegal under the equal protection clause, civil rights acts, or labor laws. As long as it is the underlying discriminatory behavior and not the speech that is being regulated, the first amendment is not offended. Under the analysis in O'Brien, the penalty exacted on speech in such cases is incidental to the governmental purpose of regulating the purely non-expressive component of the conduct. [9]
  • The Theory of Hate Speech as a Relational Harm. -- [This aspect has nothing to do with my aims, so I'm not providing a brief description for it. (See the taxonomy of harms in Note 2.)]
  • The Public Speech/Private Speech Dichotomy -- [This too doesn't apply to the situation and my proposed action.]
By this point, one should have read the framework and my notes explaining how I've applied them. If one has done so, one will observe that in choosing to deny permits to the white supremacists/nationalist and their Antifa opponents, I've applied the requisite and situationally applicable "affirmative" and "negative" free speech doctrines and tests and that I've closely adhered to SCOTUS guidance in doing so. Accordingly, I ma confident my "hypothetical" decision to withhold permits would likely stand.


Notes:
  1. See Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire. In that case, the Court explicitly recognizes discretely prevention and punishment.

    "There are certain well-defined and narrowly limited classes of speech, the prevention and punishment of which have never been thought to raise any Constitutional problem. These include the lewd and obscene, the profane, the libelous, and the insulting or 'fighting' words-those which by their very utterance inflict injury or tend to incite an immediate breach of the peace."
  2. Brandenburg essentially established the use of the "clear and present danger" test in determining whether and what speech could be interdicted or punished. The dangers themselves must fall into either or both of Category I or Category II (see below) harms from among those recognized as tortious or criminal in U.S. law (the injuries and acts that precipitate them are not, in law, construed as being mutually exclusive; for instance a Category I act/harm can often create Category II and/or III harms); harm that is solely a Category III harm is insufficient for preempting or punishing speech.

    Obviously, the category of harm I'd aim to prevent is Category I.

    (For convenience, the classes of harms recognized in U.S. law are below summarized. Some readers may care for vastly more summarized explication of the notion of "harm" than is found at the preceding links. For them, I suggest the following: Theories of Criminal Law or Freedom of Speech)
    • Taxonomy of Harms (Examples provided for harm classes relevant to the types of harm I, in opting to deny a permit, foresee as "clear and present" harms I reasonably expect to result were I instead to issue the permit and the applicants to assemble and express themselves. From a reactive standpoint, punishment, the ones I anticipate need not be the ones that indeed resulted.)
      • Category I -- Physical Harms.
        • Injuries to persons -- Examples:
          • Solicitation of murder
          • Incitement to riot on behalf of the speaker's cause
          • Reactive violence against a speaker in response to their message
        • Injuries to property -- Examples:
          • Solicitation of arson
          • Incitement to destroy property
          • Reactive violence against the property of the speaker in response to the message
      • Category II -- Relational Harms -- Some of these may occur, but I don't think one, I, can reasonably anticipate that they would merely as a result of a public protest or other socio-political gathering of the sort here under discussion and the accompanying expressions made there.
        • Injuries to social relationahips
        • Injuries to transactions or business relationships
        • Injuries to information ownership interests
        • Injuries to interests in confidentiality
      • Category III -- Reactive Harms
        • Injuries to individual emotional tranquility -- Roughly speaking, this amounts to one's getting their feelings hurt or suffering embarrassment
        • Injuries to communal sensibilities -- Roughly speaking, this amounts to one's being aghast at something expressed as some people claimed to be when Janet Jackson had a "wardrobe malfunction."
  3. Once again, positive and negative liberty rear their heads.
  4. One can get a sense of what Emerson covers in his book (I linked it, but I can't find a free version of it) in his paper "Toward a General Theory of the First Amendment."
  5. "Penalise" and "indeterminate" -- Observe that:
    1. The temporal context and focus is penalizing not proscribing/preempting hate speech. Penalizing anything is necessarily reactive, not proactive. Penalty requires an operative and extant actus rea wherefore courts can penalize its actor.
    2. The temporal context for determining whether the harm be "present" cannot be indeterminate. It need not be a precise hour and minute. In the matters of protests, having a timeframe reasonably proximate to the event itself -- in the setup of the event, during the event, in the dismantling of the event -- is sufficiently specific for this test.

      That harm may occur days or weeks prior to or following the noted periods is not sufficient. I would not be justified in denying a permit because I think some "nut job" may, the day before the event, say, riot in the streets or "raid" the hotel where many (counter-) protesters are bivouacked.
  6. SCOTUS asserted in Sable Communications of California, Inc. v FCC that government may only "regulate the content of constitutionally protected speech in order to promote a compelling interest if it chooses the least restrictive means to further the articulated interest." Also, U.S. v O'Brien established that "when government regulation is 'unrelated to the suppression of free expression,' the "incidental restriction on alleged First Amendment freedoms" must be "no greater than is essential to the furtherance of that interest."

    In denying the permit, I have no aim to regulate the content of the speech (definitional aspect) that might be presented. My reason for denying the permit is "unrelated to the suppression of free expression" in that I find that the town of C-ville hasn't the resources to manage the event and ensure the safety of the attendees. My reason for denying the permit is to prevent the "clear and present" risk of physical harm from materializing into reality (substantive aspect). Given my motives, the precision principle's substance provision applies and the definitional one does not. Anticipating and preventing harm such as that which happened to Heather Heyer is valid, given the C-ville resource paucity, as a basis for denying the permit.

    It's probably worth noting that whereas I'd not have issued the permit, C-ville opted to issue a permit and then revoke it. Ms. Heyer would be alive were they to have anticipated the violence and denied the permit, but it's too late for that now. As for on what basis one might foresee the violence, well, I'll leave it to you and other readers to search the Internet for examples of the violence that results when white supremacists march and/or host public demonstrations, rallies and protests. For my part, I'll note that just as C. Cantwell was able to anticipate the harm, so can I, the difference being that as the issuer of the permit, I'd have been in a position to avert it rather than inspire or commit it.
  7. Notice that again that the scope is with regard to a regulation or statue, something that applies "universally" within a jurisdiction, not the discrete and expedient exercise of professional judgment.
  8. This provision must be applied evenly. It is in recognition of that requirement that I wrote what I did about also denying permits to the Antifa.
  9. Here again I repeat, I would deny the permit due to the risk of violence erupting as a result of the speech, not to proscribe the speech itself.


Aside:
I guess people, you, WillHaftawaite, think I just post "sh*t" becuase it happens across my mind. Trust me. On the occasions that I do that, I'll, along with whatever idea I share, volunteer that I have remarked off the top of my head and without confirmation of the idea(s) I share.

I absolutely thought about and confirmed the plausible and probable legal validity my remarks on "permit denial" before I posted them. I might have missed something, but this isn't it. It arrive at my conclusion merely because I don't like white supremacists. As much as I "bitch and moan" about others not researching/confirming what they believe be so prior to posting their beliefs, you had to know that I did do so. FWIW, on the free speech topic, the research was done ages and ages ago; all I really had to do was "dig it up" and quickly review it.

Lastly, several folks have griped about the length of my posts. The ones that are long when I conceive them are the ones that I have a sense that a notable share of readers here may not be deeply familiar with the topic or aspect of it I've chosen to discuss. Others, like this one, are long because I initially posted something short and someone responded to it with remarks that bid to explain/justify the rational basis giving rise to the initial brief post. As goes the current topic, I thought, given how often the free speech topic appears on USMB and in "real life," "everyone" here is very well/deeply versed on the legal theory, case law, and applications of free speech principles and so on. Clearly, I was mistaken.

By the same token, I don't think the other member's tacit request that I explain myself was out of line or rudely made, so I don't mind, in such instances, doing so. I'd thought about it before I posted the "short comments," so it's not bother to share those thoughts.
giphy.gif


Sorry...

fell asleep somewhere around paragraph 10

That is what it is.....You replied with a potential challenge to my earlier conclusion and stated course of action. I provided a comprehensive explanation for my stated course of action.
 
In whose mind, do you suppose, ~400 feet one one side, and ~1000 feet on the other, "separation" in a town the size of C-ville (the vast majority of which is UVA campus and university-affiliated land), a place where one can holler that far and be heard, between groups numbering in the hundreds constitutes sufficient separation "for safety reasons" between groups like white supremacists and their opponents?

It wasn't sufficient at all! As I've said before, the police messed up! They are supposed to be separated for this very reason. If you were in charge of those permits, would you have put them that close with no barricade or wall of mounted cops? I wouldn't have. It doesn't take a psychic to know someone's going to get hurt or killed.
If you were in charge of those permits, would you have put them that close with no barricade or wall of mounted cops?

Were I in charge of issuing permits in Charlottesville, VA and aware that the permit was being requested for a white supremacist/nationalist gathering, I almost certainly wouldn't have issued white supremacists/nationalists a protesting permit -- on the grounds that hate speech isn't protected by the 1st Amendment and that it's reasonable to expect at least some of their speech would be hateful in nature -- in the town of Charlottesville. I would also have denied the counter-protesters a permit too were it apparent to me that they might attract Antifa and or white supremacist/nationalist contingents. Big cities are welcome, at their discretion, to forebear the sorts of conflagrations that result from clashes of those two groups, C-ville, and its overwhelmingly large student population, just doesn't have the resources to contain that sort of madness.

I'd have told them to submit a petition or send in written letters voicing their objections to removing the statue or reasons why it should be removed.
Question: Fox pundits declare at least once per hour that hate speech is protected. I've heard it other places than Fox, as well. Are you sure hate speech isn't protected? Speech inciting violence isn't, but how often has that shut down these people?
the problem is - define hate speech?

people seem to use that like a race card now - whip it out like you've put out the max line and move on, winner.

words continue to be redefined according to moods and people are taking "stop hitting me" as hate speech at times.

then, it is up to google to tell me? facebook? you? is it my right to tell you what is hateful? i can tell you *i* think it may or may not be but that's nothing more than my opinion that in the end is no better than yours.

why are some opinions trying to carry more weight and "judge/jury" than others may be doing?
I think if we were to hear their actual words there would be little doubt what was hateful. Speaking in the hypothetical, it is very easy to defend. Since the speakers really never got on Saturday, it may be mostly the chants from the crowds we are talking about, so who knows. I know a Jewish friend was very distressed with the "Blood and Soil" and anti-Jewish chants by the white nationalists. I've heard enough to know it sounds like hate to me.

One need only consider what such groups/individuals have in the past said to anticipate that they'd have said something similar in C-ville. That "white supremacist/nationalist" dog ain't changing its spots.
 
It wasn't sufficient at all! As I've said before, the police messed up! They are supposed to be separated for this very reason. If you were in charge of those permits, would you have put them that close with no barricade or wall of mounted cops? I wouldn't have. It doesn't take a psychic to know someone's going to get hurt or killed.
If you were in charge of those permits, would you have put them that close with no barricade or wall of mounted cops?

Were I in charge of issuing permits in Charlottesville, VA and aware that the permit was being requested for a white supremacist/nationalist gathering, I almost certainly wouldn't have issued white supremacists/nationalists a protesting permit -- on the grounds that hate speech isn't protected by the 1st Amendment and that it's reasonable to expect at least some of their speech would be hateful in nature -- in the town of Charlottesville. I would also have denied the counter-protesters a permit too were it apparent to me that they might attract Antifa and or white supremacist/nationalist contingents. Big cities are welcome, at their discretion, to forebear the sorts of conflagrations that result from clashes of those two groups, C-ville, and its overwhelmingly large student population, just doesn't have the resources to contain that sort of madness.

I'd have told them to submit a petition or send in written letters voicing their objections to removing the statue or reasons why it should be removed.
Question: Fox pundits declare at least once per hour that hate speech is protected. I've heard it other places than Fox, as well. Are you sure hate speech isn't protected? Speech inciting violence isn't, but how often has that shut down these people?
the problem is - define hate speech?

people seem to use that like a race card now - whip it out like you've put out the max line and move on, winner.

words continue to be redefined according to moods and people are taking "stop hitting me" as hate speech at times.

then, it is up to google to tell me? facebook? you? is it my right to tell you what is hateful? i can tell you *i* think it may or may not be but that's nothing more than my opinion that in the end is no better than yours.

why are some opinions trying to carry more weight and "judge/jury" than others may be doing?
I think if we were to hear their actual words there would be little doubt what was hateful. Speaking in the hypothetical, it is very easy to defend. Since the speakers really never got on Saturday, it may be mostly the chants from the crowds we are talking about, so who knows. I know a Jewish friend was very distressed with the "Blood and Soil" and anti-Jewish chants by the white nationalists. I've heard enough to know it sounds like hate to me.

One need only consider what such groups/individuals have in the past said to anticipate that they'd have said something similar in C-ville. That "white supremacist/nationalist" dog ain't changing its spots.
no one ever said they were not a hate group. not that particular one. my own questions were who gets to define hate as CNN is out there doing? hate will simply be used as a way to shut people down. YOU HATER YOU CAN'T DO XYZ...

you're fine til that card gets played on you. and rest assured if you let that card get in the desk, it WILL come back to you.
 
It wasn't sufficient at all! As I've said before, the police messed up! They are supposed to be separated for this very reason. If you were in charge of those permits, would you have put them that close with no barricade or wall of mounted cops? I wouldn't have. It doesn't take a psychic to know someone's going to get hurt or killed.
If you were in charge of those permits, would you have put them that close with no barricade or wall of mounted cops?

Were I in charge of issuing permits in Charlottesville, VA and aware that the permit was being requested for a white supremacist/nationalist gathering, I almost certainly wouldn't have issued white supremacists/nationalists a protesting permit -- on the grounds that hate speech isn't protected by the 1st Amendment and that it's reasonable to expect at least some of their speech would be hateful in nature -- in the town of Charlottesville. I would also have denied the counter-protesters a permit too were it apparent to me that they might attract Antifa and or white supremacist/nationalist contingents. Big cities are welcome, at their discretion, to forebear the sorts of conflagrations that result from clashes of those two groups, C-ville, and its overwhelmingly large student population, just doesn't have the resources to contain that sort of madness.

I'd have told them to submit a petition or send in written letters voicing their objections to removing the statue or reasons why it should be removed.
Did they overrule Brandenburg v. Ohio?
No; however, there's more to free speech than Brandenburg. Moreover, the scope of Brandenburg is with regard to punishment in reaction to speech made and the course of action I indicated is preemptive, thus not at all a punishment [1], and purposed upon avoiding "clear and present danger" [2] presented by the specific hate speech that would be expected to happen at white supremacist and Antifa attended public protests/events. It may be that individuals refer to the denial of a permit as a "punishment," but the law does not construe that as a punishment. It sees it as a proscription. Also, Brandenburg pertains to codes of law and regulations, not to the exercising of professional judgment, which, were I the permit issuer, is what I'd be doing in deciding to issue or withhold permits.

I believe I'd be fully justified in acting preemptively for in the wake of the Charlottesville events, we observe that Heather Heyer was killed and several others injured. As established in United States v. O'Brien, when the government promulgates a rule for reasons unrelated to the content of expression, and the governmental interests at stake are substantial, the regulation will normally be upheld even though it may have the incidental effect of interfering with speech. One may not like the "clear and present danger" test, but the fact is that it currently stands.


Let me explain the legal theory and case law that informs my arrival at the conclusion/decision above...For this post, the "main" post content provides the jurisprudential framework upon which my conclusion is based. Readers will find my application of the framework's concepts in the "Notes" section of the post. (If one doesn't read the notes in conjunction with the "main" post, one won't know and cannot understand what legal argument I've presented to justify my decision to withhold permits.)

There are two aspects of free speech (expression): affirmative and negative. The SCOTUS has recognized principles and doctrines from both aspects. The aspect that I'd used as the basis for denying a permit is, of course, the negative aspect. The two notions are well explained in Rodney Smolla's "Academic Freedom, Hate Speech, and the Idea of a University." (It's a typical length paper -- ~35 pages) Relevant excerpts are given below:

To "get it," one must understand the general framework of how freedom of speech "works" in jurisprudential consideration.

Affirmative Model of Free Speech Jurisprudence:
The "affirmative" side of first amendment jurisprudence approaches free speech issues by emphasizing a group of interrelated doctrines that have combined, in modern times, to create a constitutional jurisprudence highly protective of freedom of speech. The affirmative side begins with the mindset that speech is presumptively protected against any restraint or punishment, and regards any encroachment with intense skepticism. [3] Affirmative thinkers are unlikely to rest the justification for freedom of speech on any one theory, but instead point to a cluster of rationales for treating freedom of speech as a specially preferred social value. Most importantly, the affirmative side of first amendment jurisprudence emphasizes both the social value of free speech to the collective good and the private value of free speech to the individual. [4]

As a collective value, freedom of speech serves the general social interest in the pursuit of truth through the "marketplace of ideas. " Free speech also serves as a check on tyranny, and is the lifeblood of democratic self-governance. These collective theories justify free speech as a means to an end. But free speech is also an end in itself, an end intimately intertwined with human autonomy and dignity . Free speech is thus especially valuable for reasons that have nothing to do with the collective search for truth or the processes of self-government, or for any other conceptualization of the common good. 11 It is a right to speak one's mind defiantly, robustly, and irreverently, just because it is one's mind.'

Negative Model of Free Speech Jurisprudence:
The negative side begins with the proposition that the first amendment is not an absolute and that many recognized doctrines exist that permit speech to be regulated or punished. When presented with a problem such as hate speech, the negative first amendment thinker says: "Here are social policy values of enormous magnitude-equality, tolerance, and respect for human dignity-values that are, no less than free speech, of constitutional dimension. Let us employ every conceivable exception to protection for free expression that is currently recognized, so that hate speech can be deterred and these laudable values vindicated."

The negative first amendment thinker accepts freedom of speech as an important constitutional value, but, when matters such as hate speech are at issue, tends to look for ways to stretch the loopholes. The negative thinker will tend to punch holes in the many classic rationales that have been advanced to support expansive protection of freedom of speech. The poetic power of the marketplace image, it is pointed out, is tempered by experience. Grounding freedom of speech in individual fulfillment, it is argued, is inappropriate, for then freedom of speech becomes indistinguishable from any other human desire, losing any claim to unique shelter from interference by the state. Significantly, the negative free speech thinker is likely to single out one narrow rationale for elevating protection of free expression -- the significance of freedom of speech to the process of self-governance -- thus treating political speech as the only genre of expression meriting heightened protection.

How the SCOTUS Reconciles the two models:
The affirmative side of free speech thinking has, in recent history, more often triumphed over the negative. The SCOTUS has tended to accept the affirmative argument that freedom of speech is a preferred value supported by multiple rationales, extending generous levels of constitutional protection to a vast range of expression. Despite the marketplace metaphor's frailties, the Court has enthusiastically embraced it. The Court also has acknowledged that the first amendment "serves not only the needs of the polity but also those of the human spirit-a spirit that demands self-expression."
The predominance of the affirmative model over the negative has not, however been absolute. The area of hate speech is one dimension whereby the Court has seen fit, to grant way to some applications of the negative model. The SCOTUS evaluates matters of proscribing expression using several doctrines, some of which, drawn from the affirmative model, protect aspects and forms hate speech and others drawn from the negative model and that the Court accepts as legitimate grounds for proscribing and/or punishing hate speech. My attestation that I'd have denied the permits, obviously, derives from the Court's recognized negative principles. What are the various principles? (Read Smolla's paper for detailed discussion of what they entail and, with regard to the affirmative principles, bars one must meet overcome their forbearance of hate speech.)

Affirmative principles that protect certain hate speech:
  • Neutrality -- Mere opposition to an idea is never enough, standing alone, to justify the abridgment of speech. All ideas are created equal in the eyes of the first amendment-even those ideas that are universally condemned and run counter to constitutional principle
  • Emotion -- Speech does not forfeit the protection that it would otherwise enjoy merely because it is laced with passion or vulgarity.
  • Symbolism -- "Speech" is construed to include non-verbal expression, including demonstrations/protests and imagery.
  • Harm -- While the neutrality principle forbids penalizing speech merely because of opposition to its content, modern first amendment jurisprudence does permit speech to be penalized when it causes harm. The harm principle defines the types of injuries that will qualify as harms sufficient to justify regulation of speech. [2]
  • Causation -- The integrity of the neutrality, emotion, and harm principles is dependent upon the adoption of a rigorous causation rule that requires a close causal nexus between speech and harm before penalizing speech. [5] The modern "clear and present danger" test [established in Brandenburg] is the most famous articulation of the currently prevailing causation rule. Advocacy of force or criminal activity may not be enough unless "such advocacy is directed to inciting or producing imminent lawless action and is likely to incite or produce such action." [This is required because] Virtually any opinion might, at some indeterminate future time, "cause" physical harm. [5]
  • Precision -- A proscriptive regulation must meet two precision requirements (See also Smolla notes 34, 35, 54-58 and the corresponding text giving rise to those notes):
    • Substantive --> The regulation implicating speech be precisely designed to effectuate the governmental interest at stake. [6]
    • Definitional --> The terms used to identify proscribed speech be defined with a meticulous exactitude well beyond that of other routine legislation, so that speakers know in advance what speech is and is not permitted, thereby avoiding the self-censorship caused by uncertainty. [6]
Negative principles that allow hate speech to be restricted:
Modern first amendment jurisprudence does permit expression to be penalized in a number of circumstances applicable to hate speech. The circumstances by which hate speech can be proscribed are:
  • The Two-Class Theory -- The Court continues to treat "obscene" speech as not within the protection of the first amendment at all. Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire established that, in terms of content, only obscene speech can be proscribed under "two-class" theory.
  • The Fighting Words Doctrine -- While Chaplinksy repudiates "two-class" theory for all but obscene speech, the "fighting words" doctrine remains valid so long as the proscription meets the "clear and present danger" test. Thus a verbal attack directed at a particular individual in a face-to-face confrontation that presents a clear and present danger of a violent physical reaction may be penalized. [7] A statute aimed at hate speech that only penalizes such "fighting words" confrontations, and that is applied to require a governmental showing of imminent danger in every individual case, would be constitutional.
  • Content-Neutral Protection of Persons or Property -- The clear and present danger test permits speech to be penalized when it is on the brink of erupting into violence against persons or property. Once physical injury to persons or property has taken place, criminal and tort rules of general application may be brought to bear upon the wrongdoer, and it is no defense that the persons were injured or the property destroyed in the cause of free expression. There is no first amendment right to commit physical assault or damage another's property. Under the principles established in United States v. O'Brien, when the government promulgates a rule for reasons unrelated to the content of expression, and the governmental interests at stake are substantial, the regulation will normally be upheld even though it may have the incidental effect of interfering with speech. [8]
  • Discriminatory Conduct -- Just as the first amendment does not immunize physical attacks on persons or property, it does not immunize discriminatory conduct illegal under the equal protection clause, civil rights acts, or labor laws. As long as it is the underlying discriminatory behavior and not the speech that is being regulated, the first amendment is not offended. Under the analysis in O'Brien, the penalty exacted on speech in such cases is incidental to the governmental purpose of regulating the purely non-expressive component of the conduct. [9]
  • The Theory of Hate Speech as a Relational Harm. -- [This aspect has nothing to do with my aims, so I'm not providing a brief description for it. (See the taxonomy of harms in Note 2.)]
  • The Public Speech/Private Speech Dichotomy -- [This too doesn't apply to the situation and my proposed action.]
By this point, one should have read the framework and my notes explaining how I've applied them. If one has done so, one will observe that in choosing to deny permits to the white supremacists/nationalist and their Antifa opponents, I've applied the requisite and situationally applicable "affirmative" and "negative" free speech doctrines and tests and that I've closely adhered to SCOTUS guidance in doing so. Accordingly, I ma confident my "hypothetical" decision to withhold permits would likely stand.


Notes:
  1. See Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire. In that case, the Court explicitly recognizes discretely prevention and punishment.

    "There are certain well-defined and narrowly limited classes of speech, the prevention and punishment of which have never been thought to raise any Constitutional problem. These include the lewd and obscene, the profane, the libelous, and the insulting or 'fighting' words-those which by their very utterance inflict injury or tend to incite an immediate breach of the peace."
  2. Brandenburg essentially established the use of the "clear and present danger" test in determining whether and what speech could be interdicted or punished. The dangers themselves must fall into either or both of Category I or Category II (see below) harms from among those recognized as tortious or criminal in U.S. law (the injuries and acts that precipitate them are not, in law, construed as being mutually exclusive; for instance a Category I act/harm can often create Category II and/or III harms); harm that is solely a Category III harm is insufficient for preempting or punishing speech.

    Obviously, the category of harm I'd aim to prevent is Category I.

    (For convenience, the classes of harms recognized in U.S. law are below summarized. Some readers may care for vastly more summarized explication of the notion of "harm" than is found at the preceding links. For them, I suggest the following: Theories of Criminal Law or Freedom of Speech)
    • Taxonomy of Harms (Examples provided for harm classes relevant to the types of harm I, in opting to deny a permit, foresee as "clear and present" harms I reasonably expect to result were I instead to issue the permit and the applicants to assemble and express themselves. From a reactive standpoint, punishment, the ones I anticipate need not be the ones that indeed resulted.)
      • Category I -- Physical Harms.
        • Injuries to persons -- Examples:
          • Solicitation of murder
          • Incitement to riot on behalf of the speaker's cause
          • Reactive violence against a speaker in response to their message
        • Injuries to property -- Examples:
          • Solicitation of arson
          • Incitement to destroy property
          • Reactive violence against the property of the speaker in response to the message
      • Category II -- Relational Harms -- Some of these may occur, but I don't think one, I, can reasonably anticipate that they would merely as a result of a public protest or other socio-political gathering of the sort here under discussion and the accompanying expressions made there.
        • Injuries to social relationahips
        • Injuries to transactions or business relationships
        • Injuries to information ownership interests
        • Injuries to interests in confidentiality
      • Category III -- Reactive Harms
        • Injuries to individual emotional tranquility -- Roughly speaking, this amounts to one's getting their feelings hurt or suffering embarrassment
        • Injuries to communal sensibilities -- Roughly speaking, this amounts to one's being aghast at something expressed as some people claimed to be when Janet Jackson had a "wardrobe malfunction."
  3. Once again, positive and negative liberty rear their heads.
  4. One can get a sense of what Emerson covers in his book (I linked it, but I can't find a free version of it) in his paper "Toward a General Theory of the First Amendment."
  5. "Penalise" and "indeterminate" -- Observe that:
    1. The temporal context and focus is penalizing not proscribing/preempting hate speech. Penalizing anything is necessarily reactive, not proactive. Penalty requires an operative and extant actus rea wherefore courts can penalize its actor.
    2. The temporal context for determining whether the harm be "present" cannot be indeterminate. It need not be a precise hour and minute. In the matters of protests, having a timeframe reasonably proximate to the event itself -- in the setup of the event, during the event, in the dismantling of the event -- is sufficiently specific for this test.

      That harm may occur days or weeks prior to or following the noted periods is not sufficient. I would not be justified in denying a permit because I think some "nut job" may, the day before the event, say, riot in the streets or "raid" the hotel where many (counter-) protesters are bivouacked.
  6. SCOTUS asserted in Sable Communications of California, Inc. v FCC that government may only "regulate the content of constitutionally protected speech in order to promote a compelling interest if it chooses the least restrictive means to further the articulated interest." Also, U.S. v O'Brien established that "when government regulation is 'unrelated to the suppression of free expression,' the "incidental restriction on alleged First Amendment freedoms" must be "no greater than is essential to the furtherance of that interest."

    In denying the permit, I have no aim to regulate the content of the speech (definitional aspect) that might be presented. My reason for denying the permit is "unrelated to the suppression of free expression" in that I find that the town of C-ville hasn't the resources to manage the event and ensure the safety of the attendees. My reason for denying the permit is to prevent the "clear and present" risk of physical harm from materializing into reality (substantive aspect). Given my motives, the precision principle's substance provision applies and the definitional one does not. Anticipating and preventing harm such as that which happened to Heather Heyer is valid, given the C-ville resource paucity, as a basis for denying the permit.

    It's probably worth noting that whereas I'd not have issued the permit, C-ville opted to issue a permit and then revoke it. Ms. Heyer would be alive were they to have anticipated the violence and denied the permit, but it's too late for that now. As for on what basis one might foresee the violence, well, I'll leave it to you and other readers to search the Internet for examples of the violence that results when white supremacists march and/or host public demonstrations, rallies and protests. For my part, I'll note that just as C. Cantwell was able to anticipate the harm, so can I, the difference being that as the issuer of the permit, I'd have been in a position to avert it rather than inspire or commit it.
  7. Notice that again that the scope is with regard to a regulation or statue, something that applies "universally" within a jurisdiction, not the discrete and expedient exercise of professional judgment.
  8. This provision must be applied evenly. It is in recognition of that requirement that I wrote what I did about also denying permits to the Antifa.
  9. Here again I repeat, I would deny the permit due to the risk of violence erupting as a result of the speech, not to proscribe the speech itself.


Aside:
I guess people, you, WillHaftawaite, think I just post "sh*t" becuase it happens across my mind. Trust me. On the occasions that I do that, I'll, along with whatever idea I share, volunteer that I have remarked off the top of my head and without confirmation of the idea(s) I share.

I absolutely thought about and confirmed the plausible and probable legal validity my remarks on "permit denial" before I posted them. I might have missed something, but this isn't it. It arrive at my conclusion merely because I don't like white supremacists. As much as I "bitch and moan" about others not researching/confirming what they believe be so prior to posting their beliefs, you had to know that I did do so. FWIW, on the free speech topic, the research was done ages and ages ago; all I really had to do was "dig it up" and quickly review it.

Lastly, several folks have griped about the length of my posts. The ones that are long when I conceive them are the ones that I have a sense that a notable share of readers here may not be deeply familiar with the topic or aspect of it I've chosen to discuss. Others, like this one, are long because I initially posted something short and someone responded to it with remarks that bid to explain/justify the rational basis giving rise to the initial brief post. As goes the current topic, I thought, given how often the free speech topic appears on USMB and in "real life," "everyone" here is very well/deeply versed on the legal theory, case law, and applications of free speech principles and so on. Clearly, I was mistaken.

By the same token, I don't think the other member's tacit request that I explain myself was out of line or rudely made, so I don't mind, in such instances, doing so. I'd thought about it before I posted the "short comments," so it's not bother to share those thoughts.
giphy.gif


Sorry...

fell asleep somewhere around paragraph 10

That is what it is.....You replied with a potential challenge to my earlier conclusion and stated course of action. I provided a comprehensive explanation for my stated course of action.

and if I were in a lecture hall at the local university, I'd have sat quietly and taken notes.

Unfortunately, I'm not, I won't be required to take a test on the subject, at the end of semester..

I asked as simple question, an hour long lecture wasn't necessary.

(unless, of course, you're getting paid by the word)

(PS, I still dont' know if the case has been overturned)
 
Read your own connection you bloody simpering fool. They had no legal permit for Emancipation Park. They blocked the only two exits for the rally attendees.
Who's the simpering fool and who should have closely read the article, DUMMY!
"Charlottesville spokeswoman Miriam I. Dickler told Moyer that only one permit was issued for Emancipation Park — the one received by white nationalists staging the “Unite the Right” rally. However, counterprotesters did not need permits to protest that rally, she said.

“Please bear in mind that people do not need a permit to enter a public park, even when another event is scheduled to take place there, nor are they required to have one to be on streets or sidewalks adjacent to or outside the park,” Dickler said in an email."


So only the group with a permit for an affair in a park are allowed in your one-ended world?

Once again TinyTwit demonstrates her bi-ass overrides her reading skills
 
I think if we were to hear their actual words there would be little doubt what was hateful. Speaking in the hypothetical, it is very easy to defend. Since the speakers really never got on Saturday, it may be mostly the chants from the crowds we are talking about, so who knows. I know a Jewish friend was very distressed with the "Blood and Soil" and anti-Jewish chants by the white nationalists. I've heard enough to know it sounds like hate to me.
was milo wanting to talk at berkley to other conservatives hate?
how come their side can "hate" and it's excused because of the "whitewashing" done to anyone who doesn't agree with them? i don't agree AT ALL with antifa - to them i'm now a white supremacist because i don't follow along with their morality.

am i a "hate group" now?

‘Hate group’ map lists mainstream conservative organizations

why are they a hate group and why does CNN get to decide this?

like i said - the term is being used to stop counter-thought, not hate.

and i have a huge problem with that. i also have a problem with removing rights from people cause you *deem* them hateful. if they follow the letter of the law the rights apply to them also.

anything else puts your own views at risk of "thought police". you gonna be ok if your mindset is ever demonized and just go "wow, i never knew how much of a hater i was" or will you fight them from being stupid?
was milo wanting to talk at berkley to other conservatives hate?
We aren't discussing Milo. I condemned the actions at Berkeley already. Let's not confound the issue.
and i have a huge problem with that. i also have a problem with removing rights from people cause you *deem* them hateful. if they follow the letter of the law the rights apply to them also
So far, you're just saying the same thing over and over.
I don't want to go search the vids of these disgusting assholes to give you examples of their speech. You already know what they've said and you are pretending that what is coming out of their mouths is not hateful and disrespectful of entire groups of people. I'd prefer in this country that we uphold the rights of all groups to be treated with respect. Chanting Nazi slogans and screaming N!gger is hateful, and moreover it is meant to humiliate, harass and intimidate those targeted groups. Fuck that, Iceberg. Don't even talk to me if you're going to defend that.
i am trying to - as i started off - define hate speech.

i said nothing about any other group.

i also prefer all groups to be treated with respect. i would just as soon both sides stop shouting out hateful commentary to each other. but my question was not to do with this specific incident but the larger issue of banning "hate speech".

you keep moving me to some demonic side of things and pretending i'm saying things i've never said simply because i'm asking for a better definition of what we are in fact trying to get our heads around.

you can give me examples of assholes talking. i can give you examples of assholes talking. both sides. now that i'm trying to define what we can agree would be hate speech you're to "fuck that don't talk to me"

maybe that's best as you don't seem to want to listen anyway.

peace out. no hate from me.
Nor from me. I'm giving you a chance but there is no way to define hate speech without using words. The words themselves are essential.
which is why i want to know who can call what hate speech.

in an example i tried to show i'm pointing out CNN is taking it upon themselves to tell you who the hate speech groups are out there. who gave them this role? is there an official "you have crossed X line and are now an official hate group" like we do with sex offenders?

as for giving me a chance - really? you're taking the moral MY OPINIONS ARE BETTER THAN YOURS and so kindly "giving me a chance"?

keep your chances. i'm here to talk about our differences, not find out how to make you happy.
Perhaps CNN is citing the Southern Poverty Law Center for who is labeled a hate group. It's what SPLC does. Check it out.

Why don't you tell me what the definition of hate speech is, in your opinion. Or does it not actually exist as far as you are concerned? Are these groups like the KKK and the neo-Nazis not "hate groups" in your opinion? Make yourself clear.
 
was milo wanting to talk at berkley to other conservatives hate?
how come their side can "hate" and it's excused because of the "whitewashing" done to anyone who doesn't agree with them? i don't agree AT ALL with antifa - to them i'm now a white supremacist because i don't follow along with their morality.

am i a "hate group" now?

‘Hate group’ map lists mainstream conservative organizations

why are they a hate group and why does CNN get to decide this?

like i said - the term is being used to stop counter-thought, not hate.

and i have a huge problem with that. i also have a problem with removing rights from people cause you *deem* them hateful. if they follow the letter of the law the rights apply to them also.

anything else puts your own views at risk of "thought police". you gonna be ok if your mindset is ever demonized and just go "wow, i never knew how much of a hater i was" or will you fight them from being stupid?
was milo wanting to talk at berkley to other conservatives hate?
We aren't discussing Milo. I condemned the actions at Berkeley already. Let's not confound the issue.
and i have a huge problem with that. i also have a problem with removing rights from people cause you *deem* them hateful. if they follow the letter of the law the rights apply to them also
So far, you're just saying the same thing over and over.
I don't want to go search the vids of these disgusting assholes to give you examples of their speech. You already know what they've said and you are pretending that what is coming out of their mouths is not hateful and disrespectful of entire groups of people. I'd prefer in this country that we uphold the rights of all groups to be treated with respect. Chanting Nazi slogans and screaming N!gger is hateful, and moreover it is meant to humiliate, harass and intimidate those targeted groups. Fuck that, Iceberg. Don't even talk to me if you're going to defend that.
i am trying to - as i started off - define hate speech.

i said nothing about any other group.

i also prefer all groups to be treated with respect. i would just as soon both sides stop shouting out hateful commentary to each other. but my question was not to do with this specific incident but the larger issue of banning "hate speech".

you keep moving me to some demonic side of things and pretending i'm saying things i've never said simply because i'm asking for a better definition of what we are in fact trying to get our heads around.

you can give me examples of assholes talking. i can give you examples of assholes talking. both sides. now that i'm trying to define what we can agree would be hate speech you're to "fuck that don't talk to me"

maybe that's best as you don't seem to want to listen anyway.

peace out. no hate from me.
Nor from me. I'm giving you a chance but there is no way to define hate speech without using words. The words themselves are essential.
which is why i want to know who can call what hate speech.

in an example i tried to show i'm pointing out CNN is taking it upon themselves to tell you who the hate speech groups are out there. who gave them this role? is there an official "you have crossed X line and are now an official hate group" like we do with sex offenders?

as for giving me a chance - really? you're taking the moral MY OPINIONS ARE BETTER THAN YOURS and so kindly "giving me a chance"?

keep your chances. i'm here to talk about our differences, not find out how to make you happy.
Perhaps CNN is citing the Southern Poverty Law Center for who is labeled a hate group. It's what SPLC does. Check it out.

Why don't you tell me what the definition of hate speech is, in your opinion. Or does it not actually exist as far as you are concerned? Are these groups like the KKK and the neo-Nazis not "hate groups" in your opinion? Make yourself clear.

I wonder if these Trumpies ever saw themselves as having to defend Nazis when they decided to vote for him?
 
A small minority group legally marching, exercising their constitutional rights to assemble and freedom of speech, to voice their minority vile opinions is much less of a threat then the Left has proven to be by -admittedly - engaging and violence in order to deny Americans of their constitutional rights.

White supremacist did not engage in violence - rioting, looting, destroying property, committing arson and burning businesses to the ground- in a successful attempt to silence free speech at Berkeley.
- That was The Left.

White supremacist did not admittedly engage in violence in Charlottesville in order to deny Americans of their constitutional rights to assemble and to express their views freely.
That, again, was The Left.
 
was milo wanting to talk at berkley to other conservatives hate?
how come their side can "hate" and it's excused because of the "whitewashing" done to anyone who doesn't agree with them? i don't agree AT ALL with antifa - to them i'm now a white supremacist because i don't follow along with their morality.

am i a "hate group" now?

‘Hate group’ map lists mainstream conservative organizations

why are they a hate group and why does CNN get to decide this?

like i said - the term is being used to stop counter-thought, not hate.

and i have a huge problem with that. i also have a problem with removing rights from people cause you *deem* them hateful. if they follow the letter of the law the rights apply to them also.

anything else puts your own views at risk of "thought police". you gonna be ok if your mindset is ever demonized and just go "wow, i never knew how much of a hater i was" or will you fight them from being stupid?
was milo wanting to talk at berkley to other conservatives hate?
We aren't discussing Milo. I condemned the actions at Berkeley already. Let's not confound the issue.
and i have a huge problem with that. i also have a problem with removing rights from people cause you *deem* them hateful. if they follow the letter of the law the rights apply to them also
So far, you're just saying the same thing over and over.
I don't want to go search the vids of these disgusting assholes to give you examples of their speech. You already know what they've said and you are pretending that what is coming out of their mouths is not hateful and disrespectful of entire groups of people. I'd prefer in this country that we uphold the rights of all groups to be treated with respect. Chanting Nazi slogans and screaming N!gger is hateful, and moreover it is meant to humiliate, harass and intimidate those targeted groups. Fuck that, Iceberg. Don't even talk to me if you're going to defend that.
i am trying to - as i started off - define hate speech.

i said nothing about any other group.

i also prefer all groups to be treated with respect. i would just as soon both sides stop shouting out hateful commentary to each other. but my question was not to do with this specific incident but the larger issue of banning "hate speech".

you keep moving me to some demonic side of things and pretending i'm saying things i've never said simply because i'm asking for a better definition of what we are in fact trying to get our heads around.

you can give me examples of assholes talking. i can give you examples of assholes talking. both sides. now that i'm trying to define what we can agree would be hate speech you're to "fuck that don't talk to me"

maybe that's best as you don't seem to want to listen anyway.

peace out. no hate from me.
Nor from me. I'm giving you a chance but there is no way to define hate speech without using words. The words themselves are essential.
which is why i want to know who can call what hate speech.

in an example i tried to show i'm pointing out CNN is taking it upon themselves to tell you who the hate speech groups are out there. who gave them this role? is there an official "you have crossed X line and are now an official hate group" like we do with sex offenders?

as for giving me a chance - really? you're taking the moral MY OPINIONS ARE BETTER THAN YOURS and so kindly "giving me a chance"?

keep your chances. i'm here to talk about our differences, not find out how to make you happy.
Perhaps CNN is citing the Southern Poverty Law Center for who is labeled a hate group. It's what SPLC does. Check it out.

Why don't you tell me what the definition of hate speech is, in your opinion. Or does it not actually exist as far as you are concerned? Are these groups like the KKK and the neo-Nazis not "hate groups" in your opinion? Make yourself clear.
if i knew i would tell you.

is what the white nationalists did hate speech? i'd say so yes. but i'd also say what the antifa did to milo and their group hate also. hating haters doesn't make the hate ok, does it?

i'm not asking to be a dick contrary to what you seem to think. i'm asking this to establish a baseline for talking about it. you seem to find it offensive i don't simply go HATER and join the mob in demeaning them. i may be wrong but that's how i'm taking this convo so far from you.

i also never said we don't have hate speech, i have said time and again i won't take someones rights away so easily cause i don't like what they are saying.

people confuse that point far too easily it seems and take that to mean i approve of what they say or how they act. far from it but i suppose it makes it simpler for you to understand vs. talking things out.
 
The mother of the murdered girl, Heather, says she doesn't want a phone call or anything else from Trump.


Like Trump would take time out of his golf game.
He's not like President Obama who would have attended the funeral.
 
A small minority group legally marching, exercising their constitutional rights to assemble and freedom of speech, to voice their minority vile opinions is much less of a threat then the Left has proven to be by -admittedly - engaging and violence in order to deny Americans of their constitutional rights.

White supremacist did not engage in violence - rioting, looting, destroying property, committing arson and burning businesses to the ground- in a successful attempt to silence free speech at Berkeley.
- That was The Left.

White supremacist did not admittedly engage in violence in Charlottesville in order to deny Americans of their constitutional rights to assemble and to express their views freely.
That, again, was The Left.
You keep lying motherfucker. It was a nazi riot and the mayor, governor and eye witnesses have stated it.
 
was milo wanting to talk at berkley to other conservatives hate?
We aren't discussing Milo. I condemned the actions at Berkeley already. Let's not confound the issue.
and i have a huge problem with that. i also have a problem with removing rights from people cause you *deem* them hateful. if they follow the letter of the law the rights apply to them also
So far, you're just saying the same thing over and over.
I don't want to go search the vids of these disgusting assholes to give you examples of their speech. You already know what they've said and you are pretending that what is coming out of their mouths is not hateful and disrespectful of entire groups of people. I'd prefer in this country that we uphold the rights of all groups to be treated with respect. Chanting Nazi slogans and screaming N!gger is hateful, and moreover it is meant to humiliate, harass and intimidate those targeted groups. Fuck that, Iceberg. Don't even talk to me if you're going to defend that.
i am trying to - as i started off - define hate speech.

i said nothing about any other group.

i also prefer all groups to be treated with respect. i would just as soon both sides stop shouting out hateful commentary to each other. but my question was not to do with this specific incident but the larger issue of banning "hate speech".

you keep moving me to some demonic side of things and pretending i'm saying things i've never said simply because i'm asking for a better definition of what we are in fact trying to get our heads around.

you can give me examples of assholes talking. i can give you examples of assholes talking. both sides. now that i'm trying to define what we can agree would be hate speech you're to "fuck that don't talk to me"

maybe that's best as you don't seem to want to listen anyway.

peace out. no hate from me.
Nor from me. I'm giving you a chance but there is no way to define hate speech without using words. The words themselves are essential.
which is why i want to know who can call what hate speech.

in an example i tried to show i'm pointing out CNN is taking it upon themselves to tell you who the hate speech groups are out there. who gave them this role? is there an official "you have crossed X line and are now an official hate group" like we do with sex offenders?

as for giving me a chance - really? you're taking the moral MY OPINIONS ARE BETTER THAN YOURS and so kindly "giving me a chance"?

keep your chances. i'm here to talk about our differences, not find out how to make you happy.
Perhaps CNN is citing the Southern Poverty Law Center for who is labeled a hate group. It's what SPLC does. Check it out.

Why don't you tell me what the definition of hate speech is, in your opinion. Or does it not actually exist as far as you are concerned? Are these groups like the KKK and the neo-Nazis not "hate groups" in your opinion? Make yourself clear.

I wonder if these Trumpies ever saw themselves as having to defend Nazis when they decided to vote for him?
This whole conversation spun way out of control within 24 hours and has gotten into ideology land where people can bitch for months and years and never accomplish a goddamned thing. No one HAS to defend neo-Nazi's. I don't think Trump did. All this crying and whining about being called haters is ridiculous, though.
 
Were I in charge of issuing permits in Charlottesville, VA and aware that the permit was being requested for a white supremacist/nationalist gathering, I almost certainly wouldn't have issued white supremacists/nationalists a protesting permit -- on the grounds that hate speech isn't protected by the 1st Amendment and that it's reasonable to expect at least some of their speech would be hateful in nature -- in the town of Charlottesville. I would also have denied the counter-protesters a permit too were it apparent to me that they might attract Antifa and or white supremacist/nationalist contingents. Big cities are welcome, at their discretion, to forebear the sorts of conflagrations that result from clashes of those two groups, C-ville, and its overwhelmingly large student population, just doesn't have the resources to contain that sort of madness.

I'd have told them to submit a petition or send in written letters voicing their objections to removing the statue or reasons why it should be removed.
Did they overrule Brandenburg v. Ohio?
No; however, there's more to free speech than Brandenburg. Moreover, the scope of Brandenburg is with regard to punishment in reaction to speech made and the course of action I indicated is preemptive, thus not at all a punishment [1], and purposed upon avoiding "clear and present danger" [2] presented by the specific hate speech that would be expected to happen at white supremacist and Antifa attended public protests/events. It may be that individuals refer to the denial of a permit as a "punishment," but the law does not construe that as a punishment. It sees it as a proscription. Also, Brandenburg pertains to codes of law and regulations, not to the exercising of professional judgment, which, were I the permit issuer, is what I'd be doing in deciding to issue or withhold permits.

I believe I'd be fully justified in acting preemptively for in the wake of the Charlottesville events, we observe that Heather Heyer was killed and several others injured. As established in United States v. O'Brien, when the government promulgates a rule for reasons unrelated to the content of expression, and the governmental interests at stake are substantial, the regulation will normally be upheld even though it may have the incidental effect of interfering with speech. One may not like the "clear and present danger" test, but the fact is that it currently stands.


Let me explain the legal theory and case law that informs my arrival at the conclusion/decision above...For this post, the "main" post content provides the jurisprudential framework upon which my conclusion is based. Readers will find my application of the framework's concepts in the "Notes" section of the post. (If one doesn't read the notes in conjunction with the "main" post, one won't know and cannot understand what legal argument I've presented to justify my decision to withhold permits.)

There are two aspects of free speech (expression): affirmative and negative. The SCOTUS has recognized principles and doctrines from both aspects. The aspect that I'd used as the basis for denying a permit is, of course, the negative aspect. The two notions are well explained in Rodney Smolla's "Academic Freedom, Hate Speech, and the Idea of a University." (It's a typical length paper -- ~35 pages) Relevant excerpts are given below:

To "get it," one must understand the general framework of how freedom of speech "works" in jurisprudential consideration.

Affirmative Model of Free Speech Jurisprudence:
The "affirmative" side of first amendment jurisprudence approaches free speech issues by emphasizing a group of interrelated doctrines that have combined, in modern times, to create a constitutional jurisprudence highly protective of freedom of speech. The affirmative side begins with the mindset that speech is presumptively protected against any restraint or punishment, and regards any encroachment with intense skepticism. [3] Affirmative thinkers are unlikely to rest the justification for freedom of speech on any one theory, but instead point to a cluster of rationales for treating freedom of speech as a specially preferred social value. Most importantly, the affirmative side of first amendment jurisprudence emphasizes both the social value of free speech to the collective good and the private value of free speech to the individual. [4]

As a collective value, freedom of speech serves the general social interest in the pursuit of truth through the "marketplace of ideas. " Free speech also serves as a check on tyranny, and is the lifeblood of democratic self-governance. These collective theories justify free speech as a means to an end. But free speech is also an end in itself, an end intimately intertwined with human autonomy and dignity . Free speech is thus especially valuable for reasons that have nothing to do with the collective search for truth or the processes of self-government, or for any other conceptualization of the common good. 11 It is a right to speak one's mind defiantly, robustly, and irreverently, just because it is one's mind.'

Negative Model of Free Speech Jurisprudence:
The negative side begins with the proposition that the first amendment is not an absolute and that many recognized doctrines exist that permit speech to be regulated or punished. When presented with a problem such as hate speech, the negative first amendment thinker says: "Here are social policy values of enormous magnitude-equality, tolerance, and respect for human dignity-values that are, no less than free speech, of constitutional dimension. Let us employ every conceivable exception to protection for free expression that is currently recognized, so that hate speech can be deterred and these laudable values vindicated."

The negative first amendment thinker accepts freedom of speech as an important constitutional value, but, when matters such as hate speech are at issue, tends to look for ways to stretch the loopholes. The negative thinker will tend to punch holes in the many classic rationales that have been advanced to support expansive protection of freedom of speech. The poetic power of the marketplace image, it is pointed out, is tempered by experience. Grounding freedom of speech in individual fulfillment, it is argued, is inappropriate, for then freedom of speech becomes indistinguishable from any other human desire, losing any claim to unique shelter from interference by the state. Significantly, the negative free speech thinker is likely to single out one narrow rationale for elevating protection of free expression -- the significance of freedom of speech to the process of self-governance -- thus treating political speech as the only genre of expression meriting heightened protection.

How the SCOTUS Reconciles the two models:
The affirmative side of free speech thinking has, in recent history, more often triumphed over the negative. The SCOTUS has tended to accept the affirmative argument that freedom of speech is a preferred value supported by multiple rationales, extending generous levels of constitutional protection to a vast range of expression. Despite the marketplace metaphor's frailties, the Court has enthusiastically embraced it. The Court also has acknowledged that the first amendment "serves not only the needs of the polity but also those of the human spirit-a spirit that demands self-expression."
The predominance of the affirmative model over the negative has not, however been absolute. The area of hate speech is one dimension whereby the Court has seen fit, to grant way to some applications of the negative model. The SCOTUS evaluates matters of proscribing expression using several doctrines, some of which, drawn from the affirmative model, protect aspects and forms hate speech and others drawn from the negative model and that the Court accepts as legitimate grounds for proscribing and/or punishing hate speech. My attestation that I'd have denied the permits, obviously, derives from the Court's recognized negative principles. What are the various principles? (Read Smolla's paper for detailed discussion of what they entail and, with regard to the affirmative principles, bars one must meet overcome their forbearance of hate speech.)

Affirmative principles that protect certain hate speech:
  • Neutrality -- Mere opposition to an idea is never enough, standing alone, to justify the abridgment of speech. All ideas are created equal in the eyes of the first amendment-even those ideas that are universally condemned and run counter to constitutional principle
  • Emotion -- Speech does not forfeit the protection that it would otherwise enjoy merely because it is laced with passion or vulgarity.
  • Symbolism -- "Speech" is construed to include non-verbal expression, including demonstrations/protests and imagery.
  • Harm -- While the neutrality principle forbids penalizing speech merely because of opposition to its content, modern first amendment jurisprudence does permit speech to be penalized when it causes harm. The harm principle defines the types of injuries that will qualify as harms sufficient to justify regulation of speech. [2]
  • Causation -- The integrity of the neutrality, emotion, and harm principles is dependent upon the adoption of a rigorous causation rule that requires a close causal nexus between speech and harm before penalizing speech. [5] The modern "clear and present danger" test [established in Brandenburg] is the most famous articulation of the currently prevailing causation rule. Advocacy of force or criminal activity may not be enough unless "such advocacy is directed to inciting or producing imminent lawless action and is likely to incite or produce such action." [This is required because] Virtually any opinion might, at some indeterminate future time, "cause" physical harm. [5]
  • Precision -- A proscriptive regulation must meet two precision requirements (See also Smolla notes 34, 35, 54-58 and the corresponding text giving rise to those notes):
    • Substantive --> The regulation implicating speech be precisely designed to effectuate the governmental interest at stake. [6]
    • Definitional --> The terms used to identify proscribed speech be defined with a meticulous exactitude well beyond that of other routine legislation, so that speakers know in advance what speech is and is not permitted, thereby avoiding the self-censorship caused by uncertainty. [6]
Negative principles that allow hate speech to be restricted:
Modern first amendment jurisprudence does permit expression to be penalized in a number of circumstances applicable to hate speech. The circumstances by which hate speech can be proscribed are:
  • The Two-Class Theory -- The Court continues to treat "obscene" speech as not within the protection of the first amendment at all. Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire established that, in terms of content, only obscene speech can be proscribed under "two-class" theory.
  • The Fighting Words Doctrine -- While Chaplinksy repudiates "two-class" theory for all but obscene speech, the "fighting words" doctrine remains valid so long as the proscription meets the "clear and present danger" test. Thus a verbal attack directed at a particular individual in a face-to-face confrontation that presents a clear and present danger of a violent physical reaction may be penalized. [7] A statute aimed at hate speech that only penalizes such "fighting words" confrontations, and that is applied to require a governmental showing of imminent danger in every individual case, would be constitutional.
  • Content-Neutral Protection of Persons or Property -- The clear and present danger test permits speech to be penalized when it is on the brink of erupting into violence against persons or property. Once physical injury to persons or property has taken place, criminal and tort rules of general application may be brought to bear upon the wrongdoer, and it is no defense that the persons were injured or the property destroyed in the cause of free expression. There is no first amendment right to commit physical assault or damage another's property. Under the principles established in United States v. O'Brien, when the government promulgates a rule for reasons unrelated to the content of expression, and the governmental interests at stake are substantial, the regulation will normally be upheld even though it may have the incidental effect of interfering with speech. [8]
  • Discriminatory Conduct -- Just as the first amendment does not immunize physical attacks on persons or property, it does not immunize discriminatory conduct illegal under the equal protection clause, civil rights acts, or labor laws. As long as it is the underlying discriminatory behavior and not the speech that is being regulated, the first amendment is not offended. Under the analysis in O'Brien, the penalty exacted on speech in such cases is incidental to the governmental purpose of regulating the purely non-expressive component of the conduct. [9]
  • The Theory of Hate Speech as a Relational Harm. -- [This aspect has nothing to do with my aims, so I'm not providing a brief description for it. (See the taxonomy of harms in Note 2.)]
  • The Public Speech/Private Speech Dichotomy -- [This too doesn't apply to the situation and my proposed action.]
By this point, one should have read the framework and my notes explaining how I've applied them. If one has done so, one will observe that in choosing to deny permits to the white supremacists/nationalist and their Antifa opponents, I've applied the requisite and situationally applicable "affirmative" and "negative" free speech doctrines and tests and that I've closely adhered to SCOTUS guidance in doing so. Accordingly, I ma confident my "hypothetical" decision to withhold permits would likely stand.


Notes:
  1. See Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire. In that case, the Court explicitly recognizes discretely prevention and punishment.

    "There are certain well-defined and narrowly limited classes of speech, the prevention and punishment of which have never been thought to raise any Constitutional problem. These include the lewd and obscene, the profane, the libelous, and the insulting or 'fighting' words-those which by their very utterance inflict injury or tend to incite an immediate breach of the peace."
  2. Brandenburg essentially established the use of the "clear and present danger" test in determining whether and what speech could be interdicted or punished. The dangers themselves must fall into either or both of Category I or Category II (see below) harms from among those recognized as tortious or criminal in U.S. law (the injuries and acts that precipitate them are not, in law, construed as being mutually exclusive; for instance a Category I act/harm can often create Category II and/or III harms); harm that is solely a Category III harm is insufficient for preempting or punishing speech.

    Obviously, the category of harm I'd aim to prevent is Category I.

    (For convenience, the classes of harms recognized in U.S. law are below summarized. Some readers may care for vastly more summarized explication of the notion of "harm" than is found at the preceding links. For them, I suggest the following: Theories of Criminal Law or Freedom of Speech)
    • Taxonomy of Harms (Examples provided for harm classes relevant to the types of harm I, in opting to deny a permit, foresee as "clear and present" harms I reasonably expect to result were I instead to issue the permit and the applicants to assemble and express themselves. From a reactive standpoint, punishment, the ones I anticipate need not be the ones that indeed resulted.)
      • Category I -- Physical Harms.
        • Injuries to persons -- Examples:
          • Solicitation of murder
          • Incitement to riot on behalf of the speaker's cause
          • Reactive violence against a speaker in response to their message
        • Injuries to property -- Examples:
          • Solicitation of arson
          • Incitement to destroy property
          • Reactive violence against the property of the speaker in response to the message
      • Category II -- Relational Harms -- Some of these may occur, but I don't think one, I, can reasonably anticipate that they would merely as a result of a public protest or other socio-political gathering of the sort here under discussion and the accompanying expressions made there.
        • Injuries to social relationahips
        • Injuries to transactions or business relationships
        • Injuries to information ownership interests
        • Injuries to interests in confidentiality
      • Category III -- Reactive Harms
        • Injuries to individual emotional tranquility -- Roughly speaking, this amounts to one's getting their feelings hurt or suffering embarrassment
        • Injuries to communal sensibilities -- Roughly speaking, this amounts to one's being aghast at something expressed as some people claimed to be when Janet Jackson had a "wardrobe malfunction."
  3. Once again, positive and negative liberty rear their heads.
  4. One can get a sense of what Emerson covers in his book (I linked it, but I can't find a free version of it) in his paper "Toward a General Theory of the First Amendment."
  5. "Penalise" and "indeterminate" -- Observe that:
    1. The temporal context and focus is penalizing not proscribing/preempting hate speech. Penalizing anything is necessarily reactive, not proactive. Penalty requires an operative and extant actus rea wherefore courts can penalize its actor.
    2. The temporal context for determining whether the harm be "present" cannot be indeterminate. It need not be a precise hour and minute. In the matters of protests, having a timeframe reasonably proximate to the event itself -- in the setup of the event, during the event, in the dismantling of the event -- is sufficiently specific for this test.

      That harm may occur days or weeks prior to or following the noted periods is not sufficient. I would not be justified in denying a permit because I think some "nut job" may, the day before the event, say, riot in the streets or "raid" the hotel where many (counter-) protesters are bivouacked.
  6. SCOTUS asserted in Sable Communications of California, Inc. v FCC that government may only "regulate the content of constitutionally protected speech in order to promote a compelling interest if it chooses the least restrictive means to further the articulated interest." Also, U.S. v O'Brien established that "when government regulation is 'unrelated to the suppression of free expression,' the "incidental restriction on alleged First Amendment freedoms" must be "no greater than is essential to the furtherance of that interest."

    In denying the permit, I have no aim to regulate the content of the speech (definitional aspect) that might be presented. My reason for denying the permit is "unrelated to the suppression of free expression" in that I find that the town of C-ville hasn't the resources to manage the event and ensure the safety of the attendees. My reason for denying the permit is to prevent the "clear and present" risk of physical harm from materializing into reality (substantive aspect). Given my motives, the precision principle's substance provision applies and the definitional one does not. Anticipating and preventing harm such as that which happened to Heather Heyer is valid, given the C-ville resource paucity, as a basis for denying the permit.

    It's probably worth noting that whereas I'd not have issued the permit, C-ville opted to issue a permit and then revoke it. Ms. Heyer would be alive were they to have anticipated the violence and denied the permit, but it's too late for that now. As for on what basis one might foresee the violence, well, I'll leave it to you and other readers to search the Internet for examples of the violence that results when white supremacists march and/or host public demonstrations, rallies and protests. For my part, I'll note that just as C. Cantwell was able to anticipate the harm, so can I, the difference being that as the issuer of the permit, I'd have been in a position to avert it rather than inspire or commit it.
  7. Notice that again that the scope is with regard to a regulation or statue, something that applies "universally" within a jurisdiction, not the discrete and expedient exercise of professional judgment.
  8. This provision must be applied evenly. It is in recognition of that requirement that I wrote what I did about also denying permits to the Antifa.
  9. Here again I repeat, I would deny the permit due to the risk of violence erupting as a result of the speech, not to proscribe the speech itself.


Aside:
I guess people, you, WillHaftawaite, think I just post "sh*t" becuase it happens across my mind. Trust me. On the occasions that I do that, I'll, along with whatever idea I share, volunteer that I have remarked off the top of my head and without confirmation of the idea(s) I share.

I absolutely thought about and confirmed the plausible and probable legal validity my remarks on "permit denial" before I posted them. I might have missed something, but this isn't it. It arrive at my conclusion merely because I don't like white supremacists. As much as I "bitch and moan" about others not researching/confirming what they believe be so prior to posting their beliefs, you had to know that I did do so. FWIW, on the free speech topic, the research was done ages and ages ago; all I really had to do was "dig it up" and quickly review it.

Lastly, several folks have griped about the length of my posts. The ones that are long when I conceive them are the ones that I have a sense that a notable share of readers here may not be deeply familiar with the topic or aspect of it I've chosen to discuss. Others, like this one, are long because I initially posted something short and someone responded to it with remarks that bid to explain/justify the rational basis giving rise to the initial brief post. As goes the current topic, I thought, given how often the free speech topic appears on USMB and in "real life," "everyone" here is very well/deeply versed on the legal theory, case law, and applications of free speech principles and so on. Clearly, I was mistaken.

By the same token, I don't think the other member's tacit request that I explain myself was out of line or rudely made, so I don't mind, in such instances, doing so. I'd thought about it before I posted the "short comments," so it's not bother to share those thoughts.
giphy.gif


Sorry...

fell asleep somewhere around paragraph 10

That is what it is.....You replied with a potential challenge to my earlier conclusion and stated course of action. I provided a comprehensive explanation for my stated course of action.

and if I were in a lecture hall at the local university, I'd have sat quietly and taken notes.

Unfortunately, I'm not, I won't be required to take a test on the subject, at the end of semester..

I asked as simple question, an hour long lecture wasn't necessary.

(unless, of course, you're getting paid by the word)

(PS, I still dont' know if the case has been overturned)
(PS, I still dont' know if the case has been overturned)

Dude, you just saw the length of the post and opted to read none of it, and certainly not the "first ten paragraphs" as you stated, didn't you?

The first word of the post answered your question. (I'm not like many members. I don't dodge fairly posed questions.) I even referenced and applied Brandenburg in my essay.
 
Last edited:
It's starting to unravel for Trump. A friend from Fla. texted me and said there were many cancellations at his Fla. Trump hotel.
The Trump name is toxic.
 

Forum List

Back
Top